有个V字图标免费加速器

I just published a new long-form piece through OSAM Research Partners entitled “The Earnings Mirage: Why Corporate Profits are Overstated and What it Means for Investors.”

In the piece, I describe a new methodology for measuring the profitability and valuation of corporations. I apply the methodology to different companies, sectors, industries, countries and time periods. In the process, I encounter a massive discrepancy in corporate capital allocation. I examine different explanations for the discrepancy and ultimately conclude that reported company earnings are iPhone如何挂梯子 relative to reality. I end the piece by exploring the implications that this conclusion has for individual stock selection and overall stock market valuation.

Hope you enjoy!

http://osam.com/Commentary/the-earnings-mirage

Posted in Uncategorized | Comments Off on The Earnings Mirage: Why Corporate Profits are Overstated and What it Means for Investors

有个V字图标免费加速器

I recently co-wrote a piece with Chris Meredith @chrismeredith23 and Patrick O’Shaughnessy @patrick_oshag of O’Shaughnessy Asset Management. We take a deep dive into the fundamentals of Value and Momentum to understand how these factors work. Link below, hope you enjoy!

http://osam.com/Commentary/factors-from-scratch

Posted in Uncategorized | Comments Off西语助手|西汉-汉西词典 梯子是什么意思_梯子的西语解释和 ...:他伔登上 梯子 去摘高枝上的苹果 。Aquí hay una escalera. 这里有一架 梯子。声明:众上例句、词性 类均由互联网资源自动生成,部 未经过人工审核,其表达内容亦不伕表本软件的 ...

有个V字图标免费加速器

The following chart shows the distribution of future return assumptions that state and local pension funds were using to value their liabilities as of February 2017:

pension2

The average expected return was around 7.5%. How can any large fund, much less a pension fund with a conservative mandate, expect to generate such a high return in the current environment? Where exactly would the return come from? Certainly not from anything in the fixed income universe: (source: FRED)

bonds

The answer, of course, is equities. Beginning in the early 1950s, pension funds began to shift their allocations out of fixed income and into equities.  Today, equities and equity-like “alternatives” represent the primary asset classes through which they generate returns. A 2015 survey of state and local pension funds found that the lowest combined exposure to these asset classes was 61% for the Missouri State Employees Retirement System. The highest was 87% for the Arizona Public Safety Personnel Retirement System. The average exposure was around 70%, which checks with flow of funds data (source: Z.1, L.120, fixed income defined to include cash and equivalents, equity exposure from mutual funds estimated from L.122):

fundallocs

As the chart makes clear, pension fund allocations to equities have increased dramatically over the last several decades. This shift is likely to be one of the primary reasons that equities are more expensive today than they used to be the past. When a large market participant undergoes such an extreme change in its preferences, the impact is bound to show up in prices and valuations.

Fixed income securities pay a defined coupon and mature at a defined value on a defined date. Their best-case future return prospects can therefore be directly inferred from their current prices and valuations. Anyone in the current environment who tries to extrapolate the strong returns that fixed income has delivered over the last few decades will quickly run into the reality of the math itself, which is not compatible with a 7.5% future return expectation.

Equities, in contrast, pay out variable cash flows and have no maturity. Their best-case future return prospects are therefore inherently uncertain, critically dependent on the prices that investors will be willing to pay for them in the future. This uncertainty opens the door for the possibility that their future returns will meet or exceed their past returns even when they’re trading at very high valuations. Growth can always surprise to the upside, and high valuations can always go higher.

[IOS]:免费梯子应用,纯美国低延迟推荐。 - 优创博客:2021-6-11 · 前言因为之前某些原因,所众启明星辰没有再开放。梯子目前需要用到的地方还是很多,不仅仅是可众去看墙外的世界。今天优哥给小伙伴伔分享一个免费的美区V-P-N。【来自优创小伙伴推荐】应用介绍来自美区的...

pensionhistory

An article from a few days ago in the San Diego Union Tribune made a similar point: that falling pension fund return estimates are not a cause for concern, because pension funds have shown in their actual performances that they are handily beating those estimates. Value conscious investors will surely cringe at this logic. Pension funds have been able to exceed their return expectations not because they possess any special replicable investment skill, but because they’ve been lucky enough to ride the coattails of soaring valuations in public and private equity. The ongoing increase in equity valuations has pulled returns out from the future into the past, creating a situation where extrapolation of the past is almost guaranteed to produce overly optimistic forecasts.

The problem, of course, is that the people who are voicing concerns about valuation today are essentially the same people who were voicing them several years ago, when equity prices were half their current values. And they’re using the same “mean-reversion” arguments to do it, even though the market has persistently shown that it has no inclination to revert back to the valuation averages of any prior era. They overstated their case then, and so people assume that they’re overstating their case now, even though their underlying warnings may now be worth heeding.

In what follows, I’m going to explain why I believe long-term future U.S. equity returns are almost guaranteed to fall substantially short of the 7.5% pension fund target. Unlike other naysayers, however, I’m going to be careful not to overstate my case. I’m going to acknowledge the uncertainty inherent in equity return forecasting, and manage that uncertainty by being maximally conservative in my premises, granting every optimistic assumption that a bullish investor could reasonably request. Even if every such assumption is granted, an expected 7.5% return will still be out of reach.

To begin, we can separate equity returns out into three components: (1) change in valuation (e.g., change in the P/E ratio), (2) per share growth in fundamentals (e.g., earnings per share growth), and (3) reinvested dividend payouts.

On forecast horizons shorter than a few decades, the first component of returns–change in valuation–tends to be the most impactful. It’s also the greatest source of uncertainty in the overall forecast. To see why, consider that the component is derived from two terms: current valuation and terminal valuation (valuation at the end of the forecast period). We know what the market’s current valuation is, but we don’t know what its terminal valuation will be. We can assume that its terminal valuation will gravitate towards some natural average, but history has shown that such an average, if it exists, can change over time. And even if we knew what average valuations will be in the future, our estimate would still contain substantial uncertainty, because valuation is highly cyclical. It oscillates with the condition of the economy and the mood of the investor public. To know where it will be relative to its average on some future date, we need to know where in the cycle the market and the economy will be on that date. That’s not something that can be known in advance, which is why it’s impossible to reliably forecast future equity returns, at least on horizons shorter than a few decades.

The best way to mitigate the uncertainty associated with future changes in valuation is to extend out the horizon of the return estimate as far as possible. Unlike the other two components, change in valuation is a one-time contributor to total return. As the horizon of the return estimate is increased, the one-time contribution that it makes will get spread out over longer and longer periods of time, reducing its impact in “annualized” terms. As we increase the forecast horizon out to infinity, the contribution will fall all the way to zero, eliminating the uncertainty altogether. The problem, of course, is that if we extend the horizon out too far, the estimate will becomes useless to allocators. Allocators want to know what returns will be over the next 10, 20, 30 years, not the next 100 or 1,000 or 1,000,000 years.

To generate a conservative upper limit forecast on horizons of interest, I propose the following compromise. Valuations today are in the 97th percentile of all valuations in history and the 83rd percentile of valuations over the last twenty years (itself a period of very high valuations). Rather than assume that they will revert back to some past average, let’s start by granting the very bullish assumption that they will remain exactly where they are today forever. This will zero out the contribution from change in valuation, removing it from the problem altogether. It will also reduce the need to specify a concrete time horizon for the forecast–e.g., 5, 10, 20, 30 years–given that there will no longer be a one-time mean-reversion event whose effects need to be “annualized” across varying lengths of time. Our forecast will simply involve projecting out rates of growth and rates of return on reinvested dividends using known historical data.

Of course, on this approach, our upper limit forecast will be exposed to the risk that valuations will make a sustained rise to even higher numbers in the future. But that seems like a reasonable risk to accept. And if valuations fall to 苹果手机用的梯子 numbers, a possibility that seems much more likely, then the return will suffer accordingly, keeping our upper limit estimate intact.

What many people fail to initially realize is that if valuations remain where they are today, the contribution from the third component, reinvested dividend payouts, will end up being significantly depressed relative to the past. From 1871 to 2018, the S&P composite index generated a 6.92% real total return. The return on price alone was only 2.38%, which means that the bulk of the return came from dividends. Crucially, to get the full return, it wouldn’t have been enough for the dividends to simply have been paid out. They would have needed to have been paid out and reinvested back into the S&P. If they were to have instead been reinvested into treasury bills, the real total return would have only been ios能用的梯子2022:

divstotbills

This result highlights the importance of the 苹果的梯子 produced by the reinvestment of dividends back into the market. A key determinant of the rate of that compounding is the valuation at which the reinvestment takes place. If we assume that valuations will remain where they are today, multiples above prior historical averages, then the future rate of that compounding is going to be reduced accordingly. As we will later see, the effect will not be small.

The future contribution from the second component, per share growth in fundamentals, will also potentially be depressed if valuations remain elevated. As our economy ages and matures, the need for capacity expansive real investment will fall. Corporations will have to return more of their profits to shareholders. The most tax efficient way for them to do that is through share buybacks, which is why share buybacks have surpassed dividends as the primary mechanism through which capital is returned to shareholders. In terms of estimating future returns, the critical question is, will the per share growth generated from share buybacks be able to match the per share growth that the corporate sector was able to historically achieve through real investment? The answer will obviously depend on the valuation at which the shares are bought back. If valuations are going to remain elevated, then each round of returned returned capital will end up buying back fewer effective shares, which will reduce the ensuing per share growth accordingly. Later on, I’m going to introduce a rough methodology for estimating the impact of this effect–the results will be somewhat surprising.

This is what we’re trying to figure out: if the S&P stays at its current valuation indefinitely into the future, what return will it likely deliver? The best way to answer that question is to assume that the S&P had always traded at its current valuation, and calculate what it’s historical return would have been on that assumption. The calculated return can then be used as a conservative upper limit on the kind of return for that current investors can reasonably expect.

To make this calculation, we need a reliable valuation standard to use. The best standard would probably be the Shiller CAPE, but we know that its current value is being 苹果翻墙梯子 by large writedowns undertaken during the financial crisis. Fortunately, we’re now far enough away from the financial crisis to eliminate that distortion by tweaking the lookback period. If, for example, we shorten the lookback period from 10 years to 7 years, earnings numbers from the financial crisis will entirely drop out. The following table shows the impact:

ios能用的梯子2022

The current CAPE10 is 33.33, which is 136% above its historical average. By taking out the financial crisis, the CAPE7 falls to 28.44, which is 105% above its historical average. The 31% difference between these numbers may not matter much in today’s expensive market, but it definitely would have mattered several years ago when valuations were reasonable but were being made to look expensive by the distortions.

To challenge our use of the CAPE7, critics could reasonably point out that we’re essentially using hindsight to make the current lookback period a recession-free period, when most lookback periods throughout history included at least one recession with an associated earnings drop. That’s a fair criticism, but it only serves to increase the conservatism of our upper limit estimate. By using a metric that understates the market’s current expensiveness, we will make our upper limit estimate even more robust.

Looking closely at the details of our approach, we see that it’s highly conservative with respect to each of the contributors to total return:

  • Change in Valuation: it’s conservative with respect to the contribution from change in valuation because it removes that contribution from the equation, even though the contribution is far more likely to be negative than positive going forward.
  • Per Share Growth in Fundamentals: it’s conservative with respect to the contribution from per share growth in fundamentals because it effectively assumes that growth rates in the future will equal growth rates in the past, even though we live in an aging, highly-developed economy that has clearly shown a propensity for slower growth relative to the past. It’s also conservative in that it ignores the effect that today’s high valuations will have on the per share growth generated from share buybacks.
  • Reinvested Dividend Payouts: it’s conservative with respect to the contribution from reinvested dividends because it calculates reinvestment prices using a valuation measure that likely understates the market’s current expensiveness, given that the measure uses a recession-free 7 year Shiller lookback period when most lookback periods across history contained at least one recession and associated earnings drop.

The following table shows what the component returns for the S&P would have been from 1871 to 2018 if the market’s valuation had always been what it is today, CAPE7 of 28.44:

iPhone如何挂梯子

The total return would have been 3.95% compared to the actual number of 6.92%. The difference, which represents almost half the overall return, is what is lost when you reinvest dividends at elevated prices and remove the one-time contribution from secular increases in valuation. Adding in 2% for inflation, we get a 5.95% nominal upper limit total return estimate for U.S. equities.

Pension funds are therefore left to choose from the following investment menu, U.S. equity included:

table

Clearly, it would be impossible to reliably generate a 7.5% return from a diversified portfolio of items taken from the above menu. Unless pension funds plan to lever up irresponsibly or take on a massive overweight in foreign assets, they have little hope of collectively achieving their current targets. Their future return estimates therefore need to fall–by much more than they already have.

Now, we can identify at least three key risks to our upper limit estimate, all of which seem unlikely to play out:

First, valuations could keep going up. Interestingly, if over the course of the forecast horizon, they go up and then revert back to where they are today, the effect on the return will actually be negative, because there will be no net change in valuation, but some of the ensuing dividends will have been reinvested at higher valuations than those available today. The real risk is that valuations could go up and stay up indefinitely, or for the length of the forecast horizon. In that case, the change in valuation will make a net positive contribution to the overall return, which could push the total return well above 5.95%, particularly on shorter forecast horizons where the annualized effect of the contribution would be greater. But with valuations already in the 97th percentile of record history, a sustained long-term rise to even higher valuations seems like a lot to ask for.

Second, valuations could go down, and then increase back to where they currently are by the end of the forecast horizon. Suppose, for example, that the forecast horizon is 20 years. In the next few years, the cycle could turn, with the CAPE7 falling back to a trough value of, say, 13. The CAPE7 could then hover around a value of say 17 to 22 for a decade or so and then eventually return to its current value of 28 in another market boom that peaks right around the end of the forecast period. This would allow dividends to be reinvested (and buybacks and acquisitions to be carried out) at lower prices, while preventing any net contribution from a change in valuation from showing up in the overall return for the period. But if the CAPE7 is set to drop from its current value to a substantially lower value, there will be enough pain and loss for those involved in that process to make the question of the longer-term return from here less important.

Third, per share growth could exceed the averages of prior eras. Theory and evidence, however, suggest that the opposite outcome is more likely–per share growth will continue to come in below the averages of prior eras, because the population is older than it was in those eras and is growing at a slower pace, and also because the corporate sector has fewer low-hanging fruits that it can pull on to increase productivity and output through real investment. The current cyclical upturn notwithstanding, capital allocation is likely to continue to shift away from real investment towards share buybacks, which will further contribute to the drop in per share growth, given that the buybacks (and acquisitions) will end up being carried out at today’s very expensive prices.

If a shift from investment to share buybacks does continue to occur, how significant will the downward effect on per share growth rates be? To answer the question, we need a way to estimate the rates of return that real investment and share buybacks at current valuations can be expected to deliver, respectively. The following table, which I explain below, is an example of a crude way of using historical data to make that estimate:

ios可众用的梯子

We start by noting that the return contribution from reinvested dividends is functionally identical to the return contribution from share buybacks. The only difference is that in a share buyback, the company reinvests the “dividend” for the shareholder, buying shares in the shareholder’s name and thereby eliminating the unnecessary tax event that would have occurred if the dividend were paid to the shareholder in cash and redundantly reinvested in those same shares.

Buybacks are a relatively recent thing in market history, so we can assume that all of the earnings that were historically not paid out as dividends were reinvested into businesses. The only place where the shareholder “value” of this reinvestment can show up is in EPS growth. Consequently, to estimate the historical rate of return that real corporate investment was able to produce for shareholders, we compare the historical return contribution that shareholders received from EPS growth to the average “amount” of earnings that corporations historically retained and devoted to it. Similarly, to estimate the historical rate of return that dividends (or share buybacks, which are the same thing) were able to deliver for shareholders, we compare the historical return that shareholders received from reinvested dividends to the average “amount” of earnings that corporations historically used to pay them.

That’s what the table does: it divides the historical return contribution that was received from EPS growth and reinvested dividends, 1.73% and 4.55%, respectively (column 3), by the historical percentages of EPS that the corporate sector devoted to each activity, 40% to real investment and 60% to dividends, respectively (column 2).  The result (column 4), gives the return contribution for each activity per 100% of EPS spent, 4.28% and 7.63%, respectively.

What the numbers in column 4 are telling us is that that for every 100% of EPS deployed into real investment, shareholders received a 4.28% real return (which came from EPS growth). Similarly, for every 100% of EPS deployed into reinvested dividends (which are the same as share buybacks), shareholders received a 7.63% real return. We can use these numbers to estimate what the effect on the total return would have been if the corporate sector had shifted the EPS payout towards one source and away from the other.  As we see in column 6, if we assume that 15% of EPS had been retained and deployed into investment, and 85% had been deployed into dividends and share buybacks, the aggregate return that shareholders would have realized from these sources would have 苹果翻墙梯子 from 6.28% to 7.13%. In other words, looking across the entire period from 1871 to 2018, shareholders would have been better off if the corporate sector had returned a greater portion of EPS in the form of dividends and buybacks, because that activity offered a higher rate of return, at least at the actual market prices that the dividend reinvestments and share repurchases would have taken place at.

This crudely calculated result is consistent with the academic finding that corporations who favor real investment over the return of capital have historically generated lower returns for shareholders. The finding appears to extend to the macroeconomic level as well–shareholders in the larger economy got a much bigger bang for their buck when cash was returned to them as dividends than when it was deployed into capital expenditure.

We should mention that an alternative way to explain the result, likely to be favored by bearish investors, would be to argue that earnings have historically been overstated. The argument would be that a significant portion of the earnings retained by the corporate sector across history was actually spent on maintaining capital and output capacity in their current states, as opposed to being “invested” in new projects to grow them. Instead of being accounted for as “earnings”, the money deployed into these maintenance activities should have been treated as part of the expense of doing business. Had the money been appropriately expensed in that way, retained earnings would have been lower, and the calculated return on the genuine new investments that the earnings were deployed into would have been higher.

Now, the above table still doesn’t give us what we want. It tells us how returns would have been affected if a greater portion of earnings had been devoted to the repurchase of shares at actual market prices across history, prices that were much cheaper than today’s prices. What we want to know is how returns would have been affected if shares had always been repurchased across history at today’s expensive valuation level (i.e., a CAPE7 of 28.44). The table below gives us that information:

reinvexp

As you can see, at current valuations, a shift in EPS deployment from the historical 40/60 split to a new split of 15% real investment and 85% share buybacks (or reinvested dividends) would have lowered the S&P’s real total return from 3.95% to 3.81% (or, on an assumption of 2% inflation, from 5.95% to 5.81% nominal). This result is the “somewhat surprising” result that I referred to earlier. I initially suspected that the impact of shifting EPS away from real investment towards share buybacks at expensive valuations would have been substantial, but that turned out not to be the case. Corporate investment has historically delivered the same kind of return that buying back shares at today’s valuation would have delivered, roughly 4% real for every 100% of EPS invested. If past markets had always traded at today’s valuation, any effect of shifting from one to the other would have largely been a wash.

Posted in Uncategorized | Comments Off on Future U.S. Equity Returns: A Best-Case Upper Limit

有个V字图标免费加速器

It’s the fall of 2011. Investors are caught up in fears of another 2008-style financial crisis, this time arising out of schisms in the Eurozone. The S&P 500 is trading at 1200, the same price it traded at in 1998, roughly 13 years earlier, despite the fact that its earnings today are almost three times as high as they were back then. The index’s trailing price-to-earnings (P/E) ratio sits at around 12, significantly below the historical average of 16.

Suppose that I’m a hypothetical value-conscious investor who has been taking a cautious stance on the market. I look at the market’s valuation, and think:

“Stocks look cheap here. I’ve been holding all this cash, waiting for an opportunity. Maybe I should get in.”

I then remember:

“Stocks only look cheap because earnings have been inflated by record-high corporate profit margins–10% versus a historical average of 6%. When profit margins revert back to the mean, as they’ve done every time they’ve reached these levels in the past, S&P 500 earnings will shrink from $100 down to $60, lifting the index’s P/E ratio from a seemingly cheap 12 to a definitively not cheap 20.”

With that concern in mind, I hold off on buying stocks, and decide to instead wait for profit margins, earnings and (true) valuations to come back down to normal historical levels.

The year 2012 comes and goes. Profit margins stay elevated, so I keep waiting. 2013 follows–again, profit margins stay elevated, so I keep waiting. 2014 after that–again, profit margins stay elevated, so I keep waiting. Then 2015, then 2016, then 2017–each year I wait, and each year I end up disappointed: profit margins fail to do what I expect them to do. But I’m a disciplined investor, so I keep waiting. During the total period of my waiting, the stock market more than doubles in value, trouncing the returns of my cash-heavy portfolio and leaving me with an ugly record of underperformance.

To evolve as an investor, I’m eventually going to have to be honest with myself: I got something wrong here. Rather than fight that fact, I’m going to need to open up to it and learn from it. I’m going to need to re-examine the potentially mistaken beliefs that brought it about–in this case, potentially mistaken beliefs about the inner workings of corporate profitability.

西语助手|西汉-汉西词典 梯子是什么意思_梯子的西语解释和 ...:他伔登上 梯子 去摘高枝上的苹果 。Aquí hay una escalera. 这里有一架 梯子。声明:众上例句、词性 类均由互联网资源自动生成,部 未经过人工审核,其表达内容亦不伕表本软件的 ...

These questions are all well and good, but there is a more important question that I’m going to need to ask, a question that often gets missed in post-mortem investigations of this type. Specifically:

“Why did it take me so long to update my beliefs in the presence of repeated disconfirmation? I had a thesis: that the elevated corporate profit margins I was seeing in 2011 would fall back down to past averages. Reality told me that this thesis might be wrong in 2012, when the prediction failed to come true. Then it told me again in 2013. Then it told me again in 2014, and again in 2015, and again in 2016, and again in 2017. Was all of this repetition really necessary? Could I have been more receptive of the message the first time it was presented?”

Winning in the investing game isn’t simply about having true prior beliefs about the world. It’s also about efficiently updating those beliefs in response to feedback from reality. The primary mistake that I made in the above scenario was not the mistake of having incorrect prior beliefs about the likely future direction of corporate profit margins–from the perspective of what I knew in 2011, those beliefs were reasonable beliefs to have. Rather, my primary mistake was my failure to properly 苹果的梯子 those prior beliefs in response to the steady stream of disconfirmation that kept coming in. The updating process should have moved me to a different stance sooner, which would have allowed me to participate in a greater share of the returns that the market went on to produce.

The Importance of Updating in Investing: Analogy From a Coin-Flipping Game

To better appreciate the importance of updating in investing, we can explore the following investing analogy, expressed in the terms of a coin-flipping game.

Coin-Flipping Game. Suppose that you and a small group of other people are about to compete with each other in a coin-flipping game. Each player will start the game with $1,000 of play money. Rankings in the game will be determined based on how much each player is able to grow that money over the course of the game. At the end of the game, real monetary prizes and penalties will be assigned to players based on where in the rankings they end up.

Two types of coins can be flipped in the game: green coins and red coins. Green coins are physically designed to have a 70% probability of landing heads and a 30% probability of landing tails. Red coins are physically designed to have the opposite profile: a 30% probability of landing heads and a 70% probability of landing tails.

The game is divided into 20 separate rounds, each consisting of 50 coin flips (1,000 flips in total). At the beginning of each round, the game’s referee fills a large bucket with an unknown quantity of red and green coins. He then randomly draws a single coin from it. He uses that coin for all 50 flips in the round, making sure to keep its color hidden from the participants. When the next round comes along, he empties the bucket, refills it with a random number of red and green coins, and draws a coin to use for the ensuing 50 flips.

Before each flip, the referee auctions off “ownership” of the flip to the player that offers to pay the highest price for it. For each bid that a player puts out, other players are given the option of either putting out a higher bid, or stepping aside. If everyone steps aside, then the flip is declared sold.

Once the “owner” of the flip is set, the referee flips the coin. If it lands on heads, he pays out $2.00 in play money to the owner. If it lands on tails, he pays the owner nothing (and therefore the owner loses whatever amount of play money she paid for it). After each round is over, the referee reveals the result of the flip to the participants and opens up bidding for the next flip. The game goes on like this until the end, at which point the final rankings are tallied and the associated monetary prizes and penalties disbursed.

The key to performing well in this game is having an accurate picture of what each flip is “worth.” If you have an accurate picture of what each flip is worth, then you will know when the other players are bidding too little or too much to own it, and therefore you will know whether you should increase your bid and buy it, or stand back and let it be sold.

Suppose that the referee is flipping a green coin in a round. The “worth” of each flip, which we take to be the expected payout to the owner, will be $1.40. In general, you should buy the flip if it’s being offered at a price below this price, and you should refrain from buying it if it’s being offered at a price above it. Of course, any given flip will either land heads and pay out $2.00, or land tails and pay out nothing, so with hindsight you will be able to say that a given flip was a good buy even though it was priced above $1.40, or that it was a good sell even though it was priced below it. But in this game you don’t have the luxury of making decisions in hindsight. All you can do is look forward. If you do that, you will realize that over a large number of flips with a green coin, heads will tend to occur 70% of the time, and tails 30% of the time. The payout per flip will therefore tend to average out to: 0.70*($2.00) + 0.30*($0.00) = $1.40, which is the highest price that you should generally be willing to pay.  By the same logic, if it turns out that the referee is flipping a red coin in a round, then the expected payout to the owner of each flip, which we take to be it’s “worth”, will be: 0.30*($2.00) + 0.70*($0.00) = $0.60. If the coin is red, then you generally should be willing to buy a flip up to that price, but not above it.

(Note: There are other considerations, beyond the mere “worth” (expected payout) of a flip, that may prove relevant to your decision of how much to bid for it. If you know that other players are likely to try to outbid you, you might want to continue to place bids even after the price has risen above your estimate of the worth, purely in order to force those players to pay higher prices. You might also become rationally risk-seeking, in the sense that you’re willing to buy flips at prices above their worth precisely because you’re looking for a “gamble”–consider, for example, a scenario near the end of the game in which the person directly ahead of you in the rankings is only slightly ahead, but the person directly behind you is very far behind. In that case, you might have a lot to gain and nothing to lose from a gamble, so you may be willing to take it even at odds that are against you. Finally, given that your expected return from buying a flip will depend on the difference between the worth and the price you pay, you will technically need to stop bidding when the price is some distance below the worth, so that your expected return stays positive, and also so that you are able to conform with the Kelly Criterion. That necessary distance will usually be tiny, but it could become significant, depending on how much money you have left in the game. These considerations, while interesting, are beyond the scope of what we’re trying to explore here.)

To form an accurate picture of what each flip in the game is worth, you’re going to need to find out whether the referee is using a green coin or a red coin for the flip. Unfortunately, you can’t directly find that out–he’s intentionally keeping it a secret from you. However, you might be able to assign a probability that he’s using a green coin or a red coin in any given round based on other information that is available to you. Combining that probability with the probability that each type of coin will land heads or tails will allow you to build a second-order estimate of the worth of each flip. That estimate will be some number between $0.60 (the worth of a red flip) and $1.40 (the worth of a green flip), scaled based on how likely you think it is that the referee is flipping one type of coin versus the other.

西语助手|西汉-汉西词典 梯子是什么意思_梯子的西语解释和 ...:他伔登上 梯子 去摘高枝上的苹果 。Aquí hay una escalera. 这里有一架 梯子。声明:众上例句、词性 类均由互联网资源自动生成,部 未经过人工审核,其表达内容亦不伕表本软件的 ...

Returning to the game, to proceed intelligently in it, you’re going to need to be given information to use. So let’s assume that at the beginning of each round, after the referee draws his coin, he lets you and the other participants dig around inside the bucket to determine how many green coins are in it versus red coins. Knowing how many green coins are in the bucket versus red coins will allow you to assign a probability to the prospect that he drew a green coin or a red coin, given that he randomly drew the coin from the bucket.

To clarify, there are two different senses of “probability” that we’ve been using here. The first sense is the frequentist sense, in which “probability” is taken to refer to the frequency at which something will tend to happen over a large number of trials. For example, over a large number of flips, green coins will tend to fall on heads 70% of the time, and red coins will tend to fall on heads 30% of the time, so we say that green coins have a heads probability of 70%, and red coins have a heads probability of 30%.  The second sense is the Bayesian/Laplacian sense, where “probability” is taken to refer to our degree of belief in something. For example, suppose that I count the coins in the bucket and determine that there are 9 green coins for every one red coin. The referee drew his coin from the bucket. If he drew it randomly, without preference, then I can say that there’s a 9 out of 10 chance, or a 90% probability, that he drew a green coin. But this number only reflects my degree of belief that he drew a green coin–in reality, the matter has already been settled, he either drew a green coin or he didn’t. These two senses of the term may seem incompatible, but they need not be. In fact, if Laplace is right that the universe is deterministic, then they will essentially reduce to the same thing. All perceived randomness in the world will simply be the result of ignorance.

Suppose that prior to the start of the first round of the game, you dig around in the bucket and come to estimate that roughly 90% of the coins in it are green and that roughly 10% are red. From your perspective, this means that there’s a 90% chance that the referee drew a green coin, and a 10% chance that he drew a red one. Combining those probabilities with the green coin’s 70% heads probability and the red coin’s 30% heads probability, your new second-order estimate of the worth of each flip in the round will be 0.90*0.70*$2.00 (case: coin is green, referee flips heads) + 0.10*0.30*$2.00 (case: coin is red, referee flips heads) = $1.32.

Let’s now start the first round of the game. For the first flip, you’re able to successfully buy it for $1.20, which is an attractive price from your perspective, below your worth estimate of $1.32. The result of the flip comes back “Tails”, so you lose $1.20. On the next flip, you’re again able to successfully buy it at $1.20. The result of the flip again comes back “Tails”, so you again lose $1.20. Eight more flips follow. In each case, you successfully outbid the rest of the market, buying at $1.20. The results of the flips come back TTHTTTTH. After ten flips, the result then stands at 2 heads and 8 tails, leaving you with a cumulative loss of $8.00. Ouch.

You begin to wonder: if the coin is, in fact, green, i.e., 70% biased to land heads, then why is it landing so much on tails?  Uncomfortable with the situation, you pause the game to investigate. It seems that you are being confronted with two possible outcomes, both of which are unlikely, and one of which must have actually taken place.

Outcome #1 — The Referee Drew a Red Coin: You determined that the bucket contained 9 green coins for every one red coin. On that basis, there was a 90% chance that when the referee drew the coin for the round, he drew a green coin. Did he, in fact, draw a red coin? It’s possible, but unlikely.

Outcome #2 — The Referee Drew a Green Coin but, by Chance, the Flip Results Have Come Back Tails-Heavy: If the first unlikely outcome did not take place–that is, if the referee is, in fact, flipping a green coin as initially expected–then a different unlikely outcome will have taken place. Specifically, the referee will have conducted 10 flips of a coin with a 70% chance of landing heads, and the coin will only have landed heads twice–20% of the time. The flipping process has an element of random chance to it, so this outcome is possible. But it’s unlikely.

What you have, then, are two unlikely possible outcomes, one of which actually happened. To properly “update” your beliefs about what color of coin the referee is likely to be using, you’re going to have to weigh these two unlikely possible outcomes against together. The correct way to do that is through the use of Bayes’ Theorem, which we will now take a detour into to explain. Readers that are already fresh on Bayes’ Theorem can feel free to skip the next section–but let me say that I think the explanation that I give in it is a pretty good one, likely to be worth your time, even if you’re already strong on the topic.

Bayes’ Theorem Explained

Bayes’ Theorem expresses the following relationship:

P(H|D) = P(D|H) * P(H) / P(D)

We can think of the letter H here as referring to some hypothesis or belief, and the letter D as referring to some data or information that is obtained subsequent to that hypothesis or belief. Bayes’ theorem tells us how to “update” the probability that the hypothesis or belief is true in light of the data or information that has been obtained. The intuitive basis for the theorem is difficult to grasp, and even more difficult to retain in memory in a clear form. To help make it clear, I’ve concocted the following spatial analogy.

Imagine a square of area 1, shown below. Inside the square is a circle H of area P(H). Ignore the weirdness of the term P(H) for a moment–just assume that it’s a number representing an area.  You’re standing above the square with a single speck of sand on your finger. You flick the speck down onto the square. It lands somewhere inside the square. You don’t know where that is because the speck is too small to see from a distance. It could be anywhere.

ios能用的梯子2022

The question we want to ask is, what is the probability that the speck is inside circle H? Given that it was flicked onto a random spot inside the square, the answer has to be: the area of H, denoted by P(H), divided by the area of the square, which is 1. Think about that for a moment and you will see why it has to be true: the only factor that can impact the probability that a 苹果翻墙梯子 located speck is inside a given space is the area of the space.  P(H) / 1 = P(H), so the probability that the speck is inside H is simply P(H).

speck1

Now, suppose that I draw another circle inside the square and label it circle D, with an area of P(D). I then reveal to you that when you flicked the speck onto the square, it landed somewhere inside circle D. To repeat, the speck of sand is located somewhere inside circle D–you now know this for a fact.

ios翻外墙用什么

The question then becomes, knowing that the speck is located somewhere inside circle D, how does your estimate of the probability that it is inside circle H change? In other words, what is the probability that the speck is inside H given that it is known to be somewhere inside D? The way we express this latter value is with the term P(H|D), which means the probability of (the speck being in) H given (that we know the speck is in) D.

Intuitively, we can see that the value of P(H|D) is simply the area of the overlap between circle H and circle D, which we label as P(H&D), divided by the area of circle D, which is P(D).

苹果手机用的梯子

Expressing this intuition formally, we get at a simplified version of Bayes’ Theorem:

P(H|D) = P(H&D) / P(D).

What the theorem is saying is that the probability of (the speck being in) H given (that the speck is in) D is equal to the area of overlap between H and D (denoted by P(H&D)), divided by the area of D (denoted by P(D)).

Notice that if the area of overlap between H and D is small compared to the area of D, then the probability of (the speck being in) H given (that the speck is in) D will be low (see left schematic). And if the area of overlap between H and D is large relative to the area of D, then the probability of (the speck being in) H given (that the speck is in) D will be high (see right schematic).

speck6

苹果四款梯子配置教程 | 小新博客:2021-9-18 · 苹果四款梯子配置教程 2021/01/20 | 教程,资源分享 | xiaoxin | 40 条评论 | 123276 views 制作该教程是为了让更多小伙伴能快速掌握配置技能 使工具更好的服务于自己 最主要的是给一些小白指明方向,少走些弯路吧 ...

P(H&D) = P(D|H)*P(H)

To understand this equality, recall that P(H&D) is the probability that the speck is inside both H and D. Intuitively, that probability is equal to the probability that the speck is inside H–which is P(H)–times the probability that it is inside D ios能用的梯子2022 that it is inside H–which is annotated P(D|H).

Substituting the above equality into the simplified version of the theorem, we arrive at the more familiar version, presented at the beginning of the section:

P(H|D) = P(D|H)*P(H) / P(D)

In Bayesian applications, the term P(H) is called the “prior probability.” It’s the initial probability that we assign to our hypothesis being true. Subsequent to that assignment, we will receive data with implications for the truth of the hypothesis. The term P(D|H), called the “likelihood function”, expresses how likely it is that we would receive that data assuming that the hypothesis is true. To “update”, we multiply the prior probability times the likelihood function. We then divide by P(D), sometimes referred to as the “normalizing constant”, which ensures that a measure of 1 is obtained across the overall probability space.

Our “speck of sand” analogy provides a useful intuitive illustration of how the process of Bayesian updating works. We start with a hypothesis: that the speck of sand is located inside circle H (note that we chose the letter ‘H’ to symbolize ‘hypothesis’). We assign a prior probability P(H) to that hypothesis being true. It is then revealed to us that the speck of sand is located inside a second circle, D. This fact obviously has implications for our hypothesis–it is relevant data, which is why we labeled the circle with the letter ‘D’. Upon receiving this data, we update the probability that the hypothesis is true to be a new number. Specifically, we set it to be equal to “the area of overlap between H and D” divided by “the area of D.” Intuitively, that’s what it immediately changes into, once we know that the speck is inside D.

To extend this “speck of sand” intuition to broader applications, we need to understand that for any data that we obtain subsequent to a hypothesis, the hypothesis will exhibit some “overlap” with the data, which is to say that the truth of the hypothesis will represent one possible pathway through which that data might have been obtained. To estimate the probability that the hypothesis is true given that the data was obtained, we need to quantify how prevalent that pathway is relative to all pathways through which the data could have been obtained, including alternative pathways that conflict with the hypothesis. That is what Bayes’ theorem does.

The Dangers of Overconfidence

To return to the coin-flipping game, recall that you were struggling with a dilemma. On the one hand, after digging through the bucket, you estimated that 9 out of 10 coins in the bucket were green, and therefore that there was a 90% chance that the referee, who randomly drew his coin from the bucket, was using a green coin. On the other hand, after several rounds of the game, you noticed that a string of tails-heavy results had been accumulating, an outcome that you would not have expected to see if a green coin were being used. The solution to this dilemma is to update your initial estimate of the probability that the referee is using a green coin to reflect the implication of the tails-heavy result that you’ve since observed.

In truth, you should have been doing that the entire time–the fact that you weren’t is part of the reason why you’ve been losing money in the game. Recall that the coin-flipping game, like the game of investing, is ultimately a game about who is able to do the best (most efficient, most accurate) job of using available information to build an estimate of what things are worth. Here, “available information” isn’t limited to your “prior”, i.e., your initial estimate of the probability that the referee was using a green coin. It also includes the actual results of the flips that have been accumulating since the round began–those results contain valuable information about what type of coin the referee is likely to be using, information that you cannot afford to ignore.

The table below shows what a proper updating process would look like during the round, assuming that we start out with 90% confidence (prior) that the coin is green. The two important columns in the table are “Rnd Gen (H/T)”, which shows the cumulative results of the flips in the round, and “Updated Worth ($)”, which shows how our estimates of the worth of each flip evolve in response to them.

苹果的梯子

Assuming that the referee has, in fact, been using a red coin with a 30% heads probability (the assumption that we used to generate the above data), it will take our updating process around 9 flips to sniff that fact out. After those nine flips, our worth estimate will have effectively converged onto the correct value of $0.60, even though we started the process with a belief that was incorrect.

To summarize, the proper way to play each round of the game is as follows:

(1) Assign a prior probability to the hypothesis that the referee is using a green (or a red) coin, and use that probability to calculate the worth of each flip. To assign a good prior probability, we need information. There are many ways to get it. We can sample the contents of the bucket and use the observed ratio of green coins to red coins to infer a probability, which is what the referee was allowing us to do. We can study the bidding patterns of the other participants, which might contain valuable clues as to the color of coin being used. We can install hidden cameras in the place where the flips are being conducted, which will allow us see the color of the coin for ourselves. We can try to convince insiders who know what color the coin is to reveal that information to us. We can even pay the referee to tell us the color directly. Any piece of information will potentially be valuable here, if it can improve our estimate of the probability that the referee is using a given type of coin.

(2) Update that probability as actual coin flip results accumulate. For this, we use Bayes’ Theorem.

If we’re more efficient and accurate in performing (1) and (2) than our fellow participants, then over many rounds and many flips, we will tend to earn more money than they earn. The same is true in the game of investing.

Now, suppose that we’re in a new round where a red coin is actually being used, but we initially think it’s likely to be a green coin. The following chart shows how our estimates of the worth of each flip will evolve in that case. The different lines show the different worth estimates that we would arrive at using different prior green coin probabilities: 0.500 (no idea), 0.900 (likely green), 0.990 (very likely green), and 0.999 (virtually guaranteed to be green).  The correct worth estimate, of course, is $0.60, because the coin is, in fact, red. By updating properly, we will eventually get to that estimate, on each of the assumed priors. The difference, of course, will be in how many flips it will take for us to get there, and how much we will lose in the interim period from our resulting willingness to overpay.

(Note: Y-axis is the worth estimate, X-axis is the flip number in the round.  Each line begins after the results of the first flip, so the first worth estimate is already an updated number.)  

苹果的梯子

Notice that if we assign a 0.500 prior probability (blue line) to the coin being green, which is a way of expressing the fact that we have ios翻外墙用什么 about the coin’s likely color, and the coin ends up being red, we may still do OK in the round. That’s because the updating process will efficiently bring us to the correct worth estimate, even though we’ll be starting from an incorrect estimate. The process won’t take long, and our worth estimates won’t spend too much time at values far away from the true worth.

But if we assign higher probabilities to the coin being green–say, 0.990, or 0.999, per the above–and the coin ends up being red, our performance in the round is going to suffer. The updating process that will be needed to move us to a correct estimate will end up taking significantly longer, and we’ll be significantly overpaying for each flip along the way. The reason that the updating process will take significantly longer on these more confident priors (0.990, 0.999, etc.) is that a large number of unexpected tails will have to accumulate before the ensuing result will be “unlikely” enough (on a green coin) to outweigh our strong green coin priors and sufficiently alter our stance. Each one of the tails that has to build up will come at a cost–a substantial cost, given how far off our worth estimates (and our bids) are going to be.

To see the inefficiency play out, consider the performance of the 0.999 prior, shown in the purple line above. That prior corresponds to an assigned 99.9% probability that the coin is green. Even after 10 flips, where 80% come back tails, we’re still going to be assigning a very strong probability to the coin being green–93.5% to be exact. Our estimate of the worth will have hardly budged, sitting at roughly $1.35, in comparison with the actual worth of $0.60.

The next chart shows how our estimates of the worth of each flip might proceed in a round in which a green coin is used.

graph2

Macbook pro上安装的chrome浏览器,怎么才能上google ...:2021-8-26 · 2、没梯子就弄个,后续同上 本来稍次点的方法是,某度上搜一个“谷歌访问助手”插件,拖进Chrome扩展里就可众(值得体提及的是,这种不是在谷歌商店里直接获得的一般或多或少有点问题,比如总是人机验证,但只要能用一次,就能上谷歌商店弄个正版的替换掉)。

The contrast between these cases highlights the asymmetric risks associated with overconfidence in the game. If we assign a very high prior probability to the coin being green–a highly aggressive number such as 0.999–and the coin ends up being red, we’re going to retard the updating process and create significant losses for ourselves.  At the same time, if we assign that number and the coin ends up being green, we aren’t going to gain that much in efficency or accuracy relative to what less aggressive assignments might have produced. Now, to be fair, this apparent risk asymmetry is a corollary of the fact that if we are actually correct in assigning a high prior probability to the coin being green, then a situation where it ends up being red isn’t going to happen (except maybe once in a blue moon). But if it does end up happening more often than that, suggesting that we were too confident in our assignment, we’re going to pay a heavy price for the mistake.

Now, I want to be clear. If we’re genuinely confident that the coin is green, then we should assign a strong prior probability to it and calculate the worth of each flip accordingly. That’s how we’ll win the game. But we need to make sure that we have a sound basis for our confidence. If our confidence turns out to be unfounded, such that we end up assigning a high prior probability to the wrong color, it’s going to be significantly more difficult, mathematically, for us to “update” back to the right answer. Our strong prior is going to effectively tie us down into believing that the coin is the color we initially thought it was, even as the incoming evidence screams otherwise.

Insights for the Profit Margin Debate

The primary mistake that those who were bearish on profit margins made in earlier phases of the current market cycle–and I would have to include myself in that group, at least for a time–was not the mistake of having “wrong” beliefs about the subject, but rather the mistake of assigning too much confidence to those beliefs. There wasn’t a sound basis for being confident in them, first because the subject itself was inherently murky, and second because the arguments that were being used were of types that tend not to be reliable (the arguments may have been persuasive, but persuasive and reliable are not the same thing).

Looking specifically at the theoretical arguments, those who were bearish on profit margins argued that competition would eventually force a mean-reversion to occur. But what competition were they talking about? Competition where? In what sectors? Among what companies? Competition has always been around. If it represented the antidote to elevated profit margins, then why had it allowed profit margins to become elevated in the first place? If it was capable of reversing them, then why hadn’t it been capable of stopping them from forming?

Abstract theoretical arguments such as the one presented above tend to miss important details. Granular examinations, conducted rigorously from the bottom up, are usually more reliable. If such an examination had been conducted in this case, it would have shown that the profit margin expansion that took place from the mid 1990s to 2011 was not broad-based, but was instead concentrated in select large-cap companies, most notably those in the Tech industry (think: companies like Apple, Microsoft, Google, etc). Inside specific sectors, the profit margin expansion was skewed, with companies in the highest tiers of profitability seeing large profit margin increases, and companies in the lower tiers seeing no increases at all, or even decreases. These are exactly the kinds of signs that we would expect to see if increased 苹果翻墙梯子 were taking place in the competitive landscape. Something appears to be making it easier for large best-of-breed corporations, particularly those in the Tech sector, to earn high profits without being threatened by competition. Whatever that something is (and it is likely to be multiple things), there was little reason to be confident, in 2011, that it was about to go away.

Looking specifically at the empirical arguments, those who were bearish on profit margins pointed out that every time profit margins had been at current levels in the past, they had always eventually fallen back down to the mean. But what was the sample size on that observation? Two historical instances? Three? Maybe four? A hypothesis inferred from a small sample may be worth embracing, but it should be embraced with caution, not confidence. And what about the data from the mid 1990s to 2011, data that, with the exception of brief recession-related drops in 2001 and 2008 (both of which quickly reversed themselves), had been showing a clear and persistent tendency towards profit margin elevation? This is what the chart of profit margins looked like from 2011’s vantage point:

苹果翻墙梯子

If the goal was to accurately predict what was going to happen from 2011 onward, then the data from the mid 1990s to 2011 should have been weighted more heavily than data from more distant periods of history, given that that data was obtained from a period that was temporally closer to (and therefore more likely to share commonalities with) the period of interest.

Granted, it’s easy to make these points in hindsight, given that we know how the result ended up playing out. But I would nonetheless maintain that a sound evaluation of the theoretical and empirical evidence for the mean-reversion hypothesis, carried out from the perspective of what could have been known at that time, would have led to the assignment of significant uncertainty to the hypothesis, even if the hypothesis would have been retained. If that uncertainty had been appreciated, the updating process would have been completed more quickly in response to the disconfirming results that ensued, which would have allowed those investors who initially embraced the hypothesis to have participated in a greater share of the returns that the market went on to deliver.

Posted in Uncategorized | Comments Off海草博客 – 分享我所热爱的东西:2021-4-9 · 阅读更多 如何正确地访问Google、YouTube等国外网站 苹果篇 分类目录 日常折腾 标签 shadowrocket, ssr节点, vpn, youtube, 小火箭, 梯子, 科学上网, 翻墙, 节点, 苹果手机 留下评论 如何免费实现百度云加速播放 2021年3月29日 2021年3月29日 由 进击的小白 ...

有个V字图标免费加速器

In this piece, I’m going to share a mental exercise that we can use to increase the truthfulness of our thinking. The exercise is intended primarily for traders and investors, given their obvious (financial) reasons for wanting to think more truthfully about the world, but it has the potential to be useful for anyone in any field who has that goal.

苹果手机怎么上youtube 怎么才能用youtube - 天气加:2021-9-24 · 苹果手机怎么上youtube 怎么才能用youtube 科技09-24 苹果授权京东降价是怎么回事 苹果授权京东降价是真的吗 热点01-11 手机屏幕锁忘了怎么办 科技03-01 苹果声明尊重裁定是怎么回事 苹果声明内容是什么 热点12-14 苹果涨价似成定局 双卡双待大屏幕注定

As intelligent human beings, we have the ability to be truthful, i.e., to recognize and communicate the truth. We use that ability whenever we make genuine attempts to see and describe the world correctly, as it actually is. Unfortunately, our mental processes tend to be compromised by a phenomenon called “motivated cognition.”

iphone苹果如何打开Youtube可众用的苹果翻墙油管知乎免费 ...:解决苹果手机如何上Youtube,ipad如何打开Youtube,ios怎么注册Youtube油管,2021电脑PC端可众用的稳定vpn账号密码翻墙软件美国香港ios苹果iphone手机梯子安卓Android节点知乎免费推荐国外付费ssr科学上网游戏视频vpn路由器账号密码

In many areas of life, our tendency to engage in motivated cognition benefits us. That’s not a surprise–if it didn’t benefit us, then it would never have evolved as a tendency in our species. The reason that it can benefit us, even as it moves us away from the truth, is that, in many areas of life, the truth doesn’t enforce itself. It doesn’t impose consequences on those who go against it. Examples of such areas include: politics, media, sales, entertainment, law, religion, and so on. In these areas, appearances tend to be more important than reality. Outcomes tend to be decided by the question of who does the best job of persuading people and of favorably impacting their feelings, not by the question of who makes the truest statements about the world.

But there is one area of life, near and dear to all of our hearts, where the truth does enforce itself, imposing severe consequences on anyone who dares to go against it. That area is the area of speculation. To “speculate” is to put something of value–usually money, but it can be other things–directly at risk on a belief. When a person speculates, she makes herself fully accountable to the truth. If she speculates correctly, in accordance with the truth, she gains a reward. If she speculates incorrectly, in opposition to the truth, she suffers a punishment. These incentives serve to sharpen her focus on the truth. They cause her to actually care about whether her descriptions of the world are correct. With real consequences at stake, she finds herself closely examining the evidence, carefully checking her reasoning, and taking seriously the possibility that she might be wrong–things that she is not as likely to do in other areas of her life.

A simple way to force our thinking to be more truthful, then, is to tie it to an act of speculation–not necessarily in the literal sense of placing actual bets on our beliefs, but in the imaginary sense of envisioning ourselves having to place bets on them, and observing how our stances change. For any issue that we might be confronted with, if we want to get ourselves to think about the issue in a more truthful way, free from the emotional biases and distracting incentives that tend to lead us astray, what we need to do is imagine ourselves in a situation where we are forced to speculate on it, with real consequences to be decided by whether we speculate correctly. In that state of mind, truth will become our primary focus.

Entering a Truth Chamber

To frame the point in a more vivid way, suppose that there is some question that we want to get ourselves to think about in a more truthful way. We can accomplish this by imagining something like the following:

(1) There is a way to conclusively resolve the question–for example, some perfect set of experiments or tests that we can conduct to get the answer, or an all-knowing God that can reveal it to us. The details don’t really matter here–what matters is that we know that we’re going to get the answer, and we know that when we do get it, any doubts that we or anyone else might have had about it will be eliminated. (Note: if it is hard to envision the question having a conclusive answer, then either it is not being framed precisely enough and needs to be reframed, or it is about certain types of subject matter–for example, moral claims and judgments of value–that do not purport to describe any actual reality and that reality therefore cannot answer).

[IOS]:免费梯子应用,纯美国低延迟推荐。 - 优创博客:2021-6-11 · 前言因为之前某些原因,所众启明星辰没有再开放。梯子目前需要用到的地方还是很多,不仅仅是可众去看墙外的世界。今天优哥给小伙伴伔分享一个免费的美区V-P-N。【来自优创小伙伴推荐】应用介绍来自美区的...

(3) We are asked to specify things that we value in life and that we want more of–for example, money, resources, relationships, health, activities, leisure, achievement, respect, enjoyment, insight, peace of mind, beauty, admiration, something for others, something for the world, whatever. We are told that, if we vote correctly on the question, we will be given these things, in whatever amount or combination we need to be genuinely happy. And if we vote incorrectly, we will either receive nothing, or we will face a punishment, which could range from something negligible (e.g., loss of a trivial amount of time or money) to something  extreme (e.g., imprisonment, torture). As designers of the scenario, we would set the severity of the punishment based on how much urgency we want to inject into the exercise. Note that the more severe we set the punishment, the more anxiety we will be introducing into the deliberation, which can have the effect of clouding our judgment. We want to set the stakes at a sweet spot: enough to be a big deal to us and to motivate us to aggressively seek out the truth, but not so extreme as to overwhelm us with stress and impair our ability to think clearly.  For me, that sweet spot is probably: lots of wonderful things if I answer correctly, and a small loss of some money if I answer incorrectly.

On the basis of these imagined assumptions, we proceed to ask ourselves two questions. First, which way would we vote on the question? The answer tells us which side of the question we think is most likely to be true. Second, how much wavering, vacillation and uneasiness would we experience in casting that vote? The answer tells us how confident we are in our vote–and, by extension, how much uncertainty we should attach to our associated beliefs on the matter.

I refer to the hypothetical place that this exercise puts us in as a “Truth Chamber”, because being in it is like being in one of those sound-proof chambers used for hearing tests, which block out all background noise and allow us to detect tiny sounds that we otherwise wouldn’t notice. Entering a “Truth Chamber” blocks out all of the ulterior motivations that influence our cognition, and puts everything that we value at stake on the accuracy of our thinking. Unsurprisingly, in that setting, we become laser-focused on the truth, laser-focused on describing reality as correctly we possibly can. Instead of settling on the usual path of least resistance, which is to lazily embrace whatever conceptions of the world best fit with our interests and preferences, we find ourselves inquiring, questioning, searching, exploring, checking, challenging, and so on, all with the goal of increasing our chances of successfully arriving at the truth. In everyday life, outcomes tend to hinge on appearances and superficialities, and arriving at the truth doesn’t really matter. In a Truth Chamber, arriving at the truth is the only thing that matters, and it matters immensely.

Test Cases: Dangerous Ideas

In an excellent article from a few months ago, the well-known cognitive scientist Steven Pinker introduced a series of questions centered on what he referred to as “Dangerous Ideas”–ideas that could very well be true, but that we find inappropriate, offensive, threatening, and immoral. These questions represent good test cases for us to use in experiencing the mental “shift” that takes place when we approach questions truthfully, from the perspective of being inside a Truth Chamber.

So, pick a few questions from the article excerpt below, re-frame them as needed to make them sufficiently precise and tractable, and compare the different experiences that you have in trying to decide on answers for them (1) normally, without facing any consequences, and (2) from the perspective of being inside a Truth Chamber, where your entire future will hinge on whether you are able to answer them correctly, in accordance with the actual truth. Remember that even if you are not certain on the answer to a question, you still have to cast vote. It is therefore in your interest to take a probabilistic approach, choosing the answer that seems most likely to be true, given what you know.

Do women, on average, have a different profile of aptitudes and emotions than men? Were the events in the Bible fictitious — not just the miracles, but those involving kings and empires? Has the state of the environment improved in the last fifty years? Do most victims of sexual abuse suffer no lifelong damage? Did Native Americans engage in genocide and despoil the landscape? Do men have an innate tendency to rape? Did the crime rate go down in the 1990s because two decades earlier poor women aborted children who would have been prone to violence? Are suicide terrorists well educated, mentally healthy, and morally driven?  Are Ashkenazi Jews, on average, smarter than gentiles because their ancestors were selected for the shrewdness needed in money lending? Would the incidence of rape go down if prostitution were legalized? Do African American men have higher levels of testosterone, on average, than white men? Is morality just a product of the evolution of our brains, with no inherent reality? Would society be better off if heroin and cocaine were legalized? Is homosexuality the symptom of an infectious disease? Would it be consistent with our moral principles to give parents the option of euthanizing newborns with birth defects that would consign them to a life of pain and disability? Do parents have any effect on the character or intelligence of their children? Have religions killed a greater proportion of people than Nazism? Would damage from terrorism be reduced if the police could torture suspects in special circumstances? Would Africa have a better chance of rising out of poverty if it hosted more polluting industries or accepted Europe’s nuclear waste? Is the average intelligence of Western nations declining because duller people are having more children than smarter people? Would unwanted children be better off if there were a market in adoption rights, with babies going to the highest bidder? Would lives be saved if we instituted a free market in organs for transplantation?

Understandably, we have certain visceral reactions to these questions, and we’re inclined to want to say certain things in response to them. But when we entertain them from the perspective of being inside a Truth Chamber, a shift takes place. We realize that in answering them, we are no longer answering to our peers, to society, to ourselves, or to our values. We are answering to reality, an entity that simply is what it is and that doesn’t care about anything. Our focus therefore turns entirely to the truth, to describing that reality as correctly as we possibly can. We find ourselves asking questions such as:

“What’s likely to be the actual truth with respect to this question? Not what I want to be true, but the actual truth–what’s it likely to be?”

“Do I really know that? Am I sure? Could I be overreacting to something, or underreacting to something, or ignoring something, or suppressing something, or missing something important?”

“What do I have right now, in terms of evidence, to support my answer? Is the kind reasoning that I am using to get to that answer actually reliable?”

“What information can I go look at to get a better picture of the actual truth about this subject?”

The most important question that the exercise provokes is this last one. The exercise causes us to realize that, at this moment, we probably don’t know enough to reliably give answers to any of these questions, and that if we want to have strong views on them, we would be well-served by going out and doing more research. Importantly, our goal in conducting such research would not be what it normally is–i.e., to justify the answers that we’ve already committed to, so that we can “win” the debates that we’re having with our opponents on the question. Rather, our goal would simply be to get to the iPhone如何挂梯子 answer, the ios可众用的梯子 answer, the true answer, whatever that answer happens to be. This is what it means to be truthful.

How the Exercise is Intended to be Used

I’m now going to offer some important clarifications on how the exercise is intended to be used.

First, the idea behind the exercise is not for you to literally walk through it, in full detail, every time you are confronted with a question that you want to think more truthfully about. Rather, the idea is simply for you to use it to get a sense of what it feels like to be genuinely truthful about something, to genuinely try to describe something correctly, as it is, without pretenses or ulterior motivations. If you know what that state of mind feels like, if you are familiar with it, then you will be able to stop and return yourself to it as needed in your trading and investment deliberations and in your everyday life, without having to actually step through the details of the scenario.

Second, the exercise is intended to be used in situations where you actually 苹果翻墙梯子 to get yourself to think more truthfully about a topic and where you would stand to actually benefit from doing so. Crucially, that situation does not describe all situations in life, or even most situations. There are many situations in life where extreme truthfulness can be counterproductive, creating unnecessary problems both for you and for others.

Third, all that the exercise can tell you is what you believe the most likely answer to a question is, along with your level of confidence in that belief. It cannot tell you whether you are actually correct in having that belief. You might believe that the answer to a question is X when it’s in fact Y; you might have a lot of confidence in your belief when you should only have a little. Your understanding of the subject matter could be mistaken. You could lack the needed familiarity or experience with it to have a reliable opinion. Your judgment could be distorted by cognitive biases. These are always possibilities, and the exercise cannot protect you from them. However, what it can do is make you more careful and humble as a thinker, more open to looking inward and assessing the strength and reliability of your evidence and your reasoning processes, more willing to update your priors in the face of new information–all of which will increase your odds of getting things right.

Fourth, the exercise is not intended to be used as a tool to “win” debates against other people–i.e., to encourage lines such as “You would never say what you are saying right now if you had to bet money it!” Rather, it’s intended to be used as a tool to allow you to more clearly recognize what you consider to be most likely to be true, when you are being iPhone如何挂梯子 with yourself. It’s a private thing, not a public thing.

(On a side note, the concept of “motivated reasoning” has become very popular in intellectual discourse. I’ve seen a number of instances of people attempting to use it to attack the positions of those they disagree with: “Psychologists talk about this thing called motivated reasoning, and that’s exactly what you’re doing right now!” But in a debate, pretty much everyone is engaging in motivated reasoning, selectively searching for arguments and evidence to bolster conclusions that they’re emotionally attached to. It’s disingenuous for one side to “play the psychologist” and call out the other side out on it.)

[杂谈] 亲伔,你伔ios都用的什么梯子 - 果粉圈 - IT圈:2021-9-19 · 苹果 iPhone 之家 iPad之家 Mac之家 iOS之家 资源 软件之家 主题之家 装机必备 全部分类>> 辣品 IT圈 闲谈 二手交易圈 果粉圈 小米圈 华为圈 三星圈 OPPO圈 vivo圈 一加圈 ...

At this point, I anticipate that at least some readers will have the following reaction to what I’ve said so far:

“This is all great, but why do traders or investors, in particular those that put their own money at risk, need any of it?  They already have a financial incentive to be truthful in their speculative activities, so what are they going to gain from an imaginary speculation-based exercise designed to increase that?”

The answer is that traders and investors are just as exposed to emotional biases and distracting incentives as everyone else. Like everyone else, they don’t like to confront unwanted realities, or abandon prior commitments, or admit to past mistakes, or acknowledge personal shortcomings, or embark on stressful changes of course, or accept perceived “defeat” in their disputes with their intellectual adversaries. The hope, of course, is that the monetary skin that they have in the game would be sufficient to get them to be willing to do all of those things, given what is at stake. But not all traders and investors have their own money in the game–most speculate primarily with other people’s money. For those individuals, the primary incentive is not performance per se, but maintaining the confidence of the investor base, a game that depends more on appearance and persuasion than on actual truth. And for those that do have their own money in the game, money is just money, it isn’t everything. If we want to reliably force ourselves to be truthful and honest a subject matter we are investigating, we need to imagine having more important things than money at stake–e.g., our well-being, our happiness, our freedom, etc. Only then will the quest for truth become sufficiently urgent to get us to diligently prioritize truth over the other forces tugging on us.

To conclude the piece, I’m going to illustrate the potential application of the exercise by using it on myself. To that end, consider the following contentious macroeconomic claim:

Claim: “The Federal Reserve’s third quantitative easing program (QE3), implemented at the end of 2012, provided a meaningful positive contribution to the performance of the United States economy from that date onward.”

(Note: Quantitative easing is a macroeconomic policy wherein a central bank creates new money and uses it to purchase existing financial assets in an economy–for example, already-issued government bonds. In most cases, the result of the policy is an increase in the broad money supply, but there is typically no net increase in the total quantity of financial assets in the system, because the money that the central bank puts into the system is offset by the financial assets that the central bank takes out of it.There is a contentious debate among economists as to the extent to which this policy is capable of stimulating economic activity, and under what circumstances.)

If you ask me whether the claim is true or false, I’m going to want to say that it’s false–that QE3, given its timing in 2012, provided a negligible contribution to growth, if any at all. But if I’m being honest, I have to admit that my inclination to say this is at least partially rooted in subtle emotional considerations that have nothing to do with whether the claim itself is correct. Specifically:

  • In the late summer and fall of 2010, when the Federal Reserve (Fed) started giving out hints that it was going to embark on a second QE program, the market rallied. I was positioned bearishly at the time, and instead of responding appropriately to what was happening, I entrenched in my bearish stance, missing out on sizeable market gains. The experience left a bitter taste in my mouth, and made me somewhat averse to the concept of Fed intervention. It’s a fairness thing–intervention represents a sneaky and self-serving “changing of the rules” in the middle of the game, and is unfair to those speculators who get caught on the wrong side of it. I empathize with that point of view because I was once one of those speculators. (To be clear, this is an emotional thing. On a rational level, I see how silly it is. The central bank is no different from any other market force that speculators are tasked with anticipating and responding to. Speculators who ignore or miscalculate it have failed to do their jobs and deserve whatever losses they incur).
  • To say that quantitative easing works to stimulate an economy is to say that the Fed is justified in using it. I don’t want to have to say that. I don’t want the Fed, or anyone else with power, to think that quantitative easing works, because if they think that it works, then they’re going to use it more readily in the future, which will cause yield opportunities in the economy to become more scarce and asset valuations to inflate. Financial markets will become more awkward to navigate and harder for me to earn a decent return in. I don’t want that.
  • I’ve had intense debates with other people on the efficacy of monetary policy, in person and online. I don’t want to have to admit that I was wrong in those debates or that my adversaries in the debates were right.
  • Quantitative easing is something that “works in practice, but not in theory”, which is to say that people can cite empirical cases where it seems to have helped stimulate economies that were suffering from weakness, but when you analyze what it actually entails at a fundamental level–the swapping of low-yield treasury bonds for low-yield bank deposits, two asset types that are roughly identical to each other–the theoretical basis for expecting a meaningful impact on an economy is weak. I’m a “theory” kind of person, I don’t like approaches to economics that casually bypass theory, and I don’t want those economists who have been pushing for such approaches to be rewarded with the satisfaction of having been right.

So those are my emotional biases. They aren’t really all that strong at this point, but they’re biases nonetheless. Their potential to distort my thinking is augmented by the fact that I don’t have to worry about being wrong in my views on the subject. There’s no way to know for sure whether QE3 was a meaningful benefit to the economy–there’s no reliable experiment that we can conduct to conclusively resolve the question. I’m therefore left with free rein to confidently think and say whatever I want on the topic, without fear of consequences.

Now, let’s set up a Truth Chamber on the question, to see if my deliberations and on the subject change when real consequences are held over me. We obviously need to make the claim more precise and amenable to resolution. Let’s translate “meaningful” into something like 0.25%.

Claim: “The Federal Reserve’s third quantitative easing program added an annual 0.25% (or more) to the real growth of the United States economy from its announcement in September 2012 to its September 2014 completion.”

This form of the question is more precise and easier to resolve. The way to resolve it is to literally create the counterfactual: rewind the universe back to September 2012 and let the U.S. economy grow from that point onward without QE3. If the growth rate with QE3 (which we already have data for) ends up being at least 0.25% higher the growth rate without QE3 (which we would get data for from the counterfactual), then the claim will have been shown to be true. Otherwise, it will have been shown to be false. To be fair, any outcome from this form of the experiment will likely have random variation embedded in it. To deal with that variation, we can simply run the rewind experiment a million times over: half the time with QE3, half the time without it. If the average growth rate in the trials with QE3 exceeds the average growth rate in the trials without QE3 by at least 0.25%, then the claim will have been proven to be true. And if not, then the claim will have been proven to be false.

Obviously, we can’t do this actual experiment. But we can imagine it being done–by God, or the White Queen, or whoever. Let’s imagine, then, that it is actually going to be done, and that I have been placed inside a Truth Chamber, forced to cast a secret vote on what the result will be.  If I vote correctly, I will be rewarded with a plentiful supply of all of the things that I value in life. If I vote incorrectly, then I will walk away with nothing.

Which way would I vote?

When I envision myself in the scenario, the first thing that happens is that my stomach tightens. My concentration sharpens and my mind focuses in on the claim. This is no longer about ego, or reputation, or grudges, or saving face. It’s about one thing and one thing alone: getting to the truth of the matter. I need to vote correctly, period.

Upon reflection, I would still say that the claim is “false”, that the difference in growth rates with and without QE3 would not have exceeded 0.25%. But unlike before, I find myself strongly questioning that vote. The stated number, 0.25%, is not a very large number, so my margin for error is not very high. If we were to set the number at something like 1%, I would be confident in voting false, but 0.25% is small enough to make me worry about being wrong.  With that said, it’s 0.25% annually over a two year period (2012 – 2014), so it’s more than just a blip.

With respect to the theory, QE may be a mere asset swap, but it has the effect of lowering long-term interest rates relative to what they would be without QE, which encourages potential homeowners and corporations to borrow. It also boosts asset prices, creating a wealth effect for the upper class that improves confidence and encourages spending. Neither of these effects was probably very large in the 2012 – 2014 period, but they still count for something. Also worth mentioning is the potential placebo effect of QE–right or wrong, many people 苹果的梯子 QE to be efficacious, and that belief itself could have been stimulative to economic activity. Taking potential multipliers and nonlinearities into consideration, could the combined impact of these factors on the housing market, the corporate lending market, the equity market, and the general level of confidence and risk appetite in the U.S. economy have been sufficient to have added 0.25% annually in growth during the two year period? I have to admit, I’m not sure. I’m nervous to answer either way.

With respect to the empirical evidence, there have only been a handful of historical instances in which large QE programs have been implemented to stimulate weak economies. A recovery occurred in each of these instances, but it’s difficult to draw much of a conclusion from that fact, first because the sample size is very small, and second because there are an infinite number of potential confounding factors other than QE that can explain the observed result, the most important of which is the fact that weak economies tend to eventually recover 苹果翻墙梯子 in time, without policymaker intervention. Still, the fact remains that in all of the historical instances that we know of in which QE was used to stimulate a weakened economy–the U.S. in the 1930s, Japan in the early naughts, and then the U.S., Europe and Japan in the current cycle–the economy eventually ended up improving. That fact has to count for something.

What the exercise reveals to me, then, is that I am not confident in rejecting the claim that QE3 had a meaningful positive impact on U.S. growth, where “meaningful” is defined to be 0.25% or more annually over the two year period. Whatever belief I might have about that claim, I need to recognize that it comes with substantial uncertainty.

Interestingly, one claim that I iPhone如何挂梯子 be highly confident in rejecting, if I were inside a Truth Chamber, is the claim, put forward by certain fringe opponents of QE, that QE3 actually reduced growth in the US economy. That claim conflicts both with both economic theory and the available empirical evidence. If we were to run the experiment a million times over, with and without QE3, I would have no hesitation in betting against the claim that the QE3 trials would produce a 苹果翻墙梯子 average growth number than the non-QE3 trials. I would also be highly confident in rejecting the claim that QE, when used in the standard way to stimulate a weakened economy, creates a meaningful risk of an inflation spiral, as its opponents once warned. The actual results–in the US and elsewhere–seem to have conclusively disproven that claim.

If there is a final insight for me to glean from the exercise, then, it is probably this: Looking back at the Fed’s decision in hindsight, from the perspective of my own beliefs expressed honestly and truthfully, I would have to say that the Fed got things right when it decided to implement QE in 2012. There is a reasonable chance that the program worked to improve growth by a small but meaningful amount, and the program did not introduce any risks to price stability. Put simply, QE was a good risk-reward proposition for the Fed to take.

苹果手机用的梯子

外贸行业老鸟推荐 稳定高速的梯子 - 简书:外贸行业老鸟推荐 稳定高速的梯子 外贸行业知名VNP。稳定运行多年。带宽100M-1000M!安桌,苹果,电脑,平板,MAC所有设备都支持!外贸的小伙伴伔,google,Facebook,YouTube,whatsapp,Instagram,Pinterest,kakaotalk,twitter ...

Posted in Uncategorized | Comments Off on Speculation in a Truth Chamber

有个V字图标免费加速器

Looking back at asset class performance over the course of market history, we notice a hierarchy of excess returns.  Small caps generated excess returns over broad equities, which generated excess returns over corporate bonds, which generated excess returns over treasury bonds, which generated excess returns over treasury bills (cash), and so on.  This hierarchy is illustrated in the chart and table below, which show cumulative returns and performance metrics for the above asset classes from January 1926 to March 2017 (source: Ibbotson, CRSP).

(Note: To ensure a fair and accurate comparison between equities and fixed income asset classes, we express returns and drawdowns in real, inflation-adjusted terms.  We calculate volatilities and Sharpe Ratios using real absolute monthly returns, rather than nominal monthly returns over treasury bills.)

trusasset

苹果手机用的梯子

The observed hierarchy represents a puzzle for the efficient market hypothesis.  If markets are efficient, why do some asset classes end up being priced to deliver such large excess returns over others?  An efficient market is not supposed to allow investors to generate outsized returns by doing easy things.  Yet, historically, the market allowed investors to earn an extra 4% simply by choosing equities over long-term bonds, and an extra 2% simply by choosing small caps inside the equity space.  What was the rationale for that?

The usual answer given is risk.  Different types of assets expose investors to different levels of risk.  Risk requires compensation, which is paid in the form of a higher return.  The additional 4% that equity investors earned over bond investors did not come free, but represented payment for the increased risk that equity investing entails.  Likewise, the 2% bonus that small cap investors earned over the broad market was compensation for the greater risk associated with small companies.

A better answer, in my view, is that investors didn’t know the future.  They didn’t know that equity earnings and dividends were going to grow at the pace that they did.  They didn’t know that small cap earnings and dividends were going to grow at an even faster pace.  They didn’t know that inflation was going to have the detrimental long-term effects on real bond returns that it had.  And so on.  Amid this lack of future knowledge, they ended up pricing equities to outperform bonds by 4%, and small caps to outperform the broad market by 2%.  Will we see a similar outcome going forward?  Maybe.  But probably not.

Let’s put aside the question of whether differences in “risk”, whatever that term is used to mean, can actually justify the differences in excess returns seen in the above table.  In what follows, I’m going to argue that if they can, then as markets develop and adapt over time, those excess returns should fall.  Risk assets should become more expensive, and the cost of capital paid by risk issuers should come down.

The argument is admittedly trivial.  I’m effectively saying that improvements in the way a market functions should lead to reductions in the costs that those who use it–those who seek capital–should have to pay.  Who would disagree?  Sustainable reduction in issuer cost is precisely what “progress” in a market is taken to mean.  Unfortunately, when we flip the point around, and say that the universe of risk assets should grow more expensive in response to improvements, people get concerned, even though the exact same thing is being said.

To be clear, the argument is normative, not descriptive.  It’s an argument about what should happen, given a certain assumption about the justification for excess returns.  It’s not an argument about what actually has happened, or about what actually will happen.  As a factual matter, on average, the universe of risk assets has become more expensive over time, and implied future returns have come down.  The considerations to be discussed in this piece may or may not be responsible for that change.

We tend to use the word “risk” loosely.  It needs a precise definition.  In the current context, let “risk” refer to any exposure to an unattractive or unwanted possibility.  To the extent that such an exposure can be avoided, it warrants compensation.  Rational investors will demand compensation for it.  That compensation will typically come in the form of a return–specifically, an excess return over alternatives that successfully avoid it, i.e., “risk-free” alternatives.

Macbook pro上安装的chrome浏览器,怎么才能上google ...:2021-8-26 · 2、没梯子就弄个,后续同上 本来稍次点的方法是,某度上搜一个“谷歌访问助手”插件,拖进Chrome扩展里就可众(值得体提及的是,这种不是在谷歌商店里直接获得的一般或多或少有点问题,比如总是人机验证,但只要能用一次,就能上谷歌商店弄个正版的替换掉)。

Price Risk and Inflation Risk

Suppose that there are two types of assets in the asset universe.

(1) Zero Coupon 10 Yr Government Bond, Par Value $100.

(2) Cash Deposited at an Insured Bank — expected long-term return, 2%.

The question: What is fair value for the government bond?

The proper way to answer the question is to identify all of the differences between the government bond and the cash, and to then settle on a rate of return (and therefore a price) that fairly compensates for them, in total.

The primary difference between the government bond and the cash is that the cash is liquid.  You can use it to buy things, or to take advantage of better investment opportunities that might emerge.  Of course, you can do the same with the government bond, but you can’t do it directly.  You have to sell the bond to someone else.  What will its price in the market be?  How will its price behave over time?  You don’t know.  When you go to actually sell it, the price could end up being lower than the price you paid for it, in which case accessing your money will require you to accept a loss.  We call exposure to that possibility ios可众用的梯子.  The bond contains it, cash does not.  To compensate, the bond should offer an excess return over cash, which is the “price-risk-free” alternative.

To fully dismiss the price risk in a government bond investment, you would have to assume total illiquidity in it.  Total illiquidity is an extreme cost that dramatically increases the excess return necessary to draw an investor in.  That said, price risk is a threat to more than just your liquidity.  It’s a threat to your peace of mind, to your measured performance as an investor or manager, and to your ability to remain in leveraged trades.  And so even if you have no reason to want liquid access to your money, no reason to care about illiquidity, the risk that the price of an investment might fall will still warrants some compensation.

A second category of risk is inflation risk.  Inflation risk is exposure to the possibility that the rate of inflation might unexpectedly increase, reducing the real value of a security’s future payouts.  The cash is offering payouts tied to the short-term rate, which (typically) gets adjusted in response to changes in inflation.  It therefore carries a measure of protection from that risk.  The bond, in contrast, is offering a fixed payout 10 years from now, and is fully exposed to the risk.  To compensate for the difference, the bond should offer an excess return over cash.

Returning to the scenario, let’s assume that you assess all of the differences between the bond and cash, to include the bond’s price risk and inflation risk, and conclude that a 2% excess return in the bond is warranted.  Your estimate of fair value, then, will be $67.55, which equates to a 4% yield-to-maturity (YTM).

Fundamental Risk: An Introduction to Lotto Shares

A security is a stream of cash flows and payouts.  Fundamental risk is risk to those cash flows and payouts–the possibility that they might not pay out.  We can illustrate its impact with an example.

In the previous scenario, you estimated fair value for the government bond to be $67.55, 4% YTM.  Let’s assume that you’re now forced to invest your entire net worth into either that bond at that price, or into a new type of security that’s been introduced into the market, a “Lotto Share.”

To reiterate, your choice:

(1) Zero Coupon 10 Yr Government Bonds, 4% YTM, Price $67.55, Par Value $100.

(2) Zero Coupon 10 Yr ios翻外墙用什么, Class “A”.

Lotto Share: A government bond with a random payout.  Lotto Shares are issued in separate share classes.  At the maturity date of each share class, the government flips a fair coin.  If the coin ends up heads (50% chance), the government exchanges each outstanding share in the share class for a payment of $200.  If the coin ends up tails (50% chance), the government makes no exchange, and each outstanding share in the share class expires worthless.

Before you make your choice, note that the Lotto Shares being offered all come from the same class, Class “A.”  All of their payouts will therefore be decided by the same single coin flip, to take place at maturity 10 years from now.

The question:  What is fair value for a Lotto Share?

To answer the question, try to imagine that you’re actually in the scenario, forced to choose between the two options.  What price would Lotto Shares have to sell at in order for you to choose to invest  in them?  Would $67.55 be appropriate?  How about $50?  $25?  $10?  $5?  $1?  One penny?  Is there any price that would interest you?

It goes without saying that your answer will depend on whether you can diversify among the two options.  Having the entirety of your portfolio, or even a sizeable portion thereof, invested in a security that has a 50% chance of becoming worthless represents an enormous risk.  You would need the prospect of an enormous potential reward in order to take it–if you were willing to take it at all.  But if you have the option to invest much smaller portions of your portfolio into the security, if not simply for the “fun” of doing so, the potential reward won’t need to be as large.

Assume that you do have the ability to diversify between the two options.  The question will then take on a second dimension: allocation.  At each potential price for Lotto Shares, ranging from zero to infinity, how much of your portfolio would you choose to allocate to them?

Let’s assume that Lotto Shares are selling for the same price as normal government bonds, $67.55.  How much of your portfolio would you choose to put into them?  If you’re like most investors, your answer will be 0%, i.e., nothing.  To understand why, notice that Lotto Shares have the same expected (average) payout as normal government bonds, $100 ($200 * 50% + $0 * 50% = $100).  The difference is that they pay that amount with double-or-nothing risk–at maturity, you’re either going to receive $200 or $0.  That risk requires compensation–an excess return–over the risk-free alternative.  Lotto Shares priced identically to normal government bonds (the risk-free alternative) do not offer such compensation, therefore you’re not going to want to allocate anything to them.  You’ll put everything in the normal government bond.

Now, in theory, we can envision specific situations where you might actually want double-or-nothing risk.  For example, you might need lifesaving medical treatment, and only have half the money needed to cover the cost.  In that case, you’ll be willing to make the bet even without compensation–just flip the damn coin.  If it comes back heads, you’ll survive, if it comes back tails… who cares, you would have died anyways.  Alternatively, you might be managing other people’s money under a perverse “heads-you-win, tails-they-lose” incentive arrangement.  In that case, you might be perfectly comfortable submitting the outcome to a coin flip, without receiving any extra compensation for the risk–it’s not a risk to you.  But in any normal, healthy investment situation, that’s not going to be the case.  Risk will be unwelcome, and you won’t willingly take it on unless you get paid to do so.

Note that the same point holds for price risk and inflation risk.  Prices can go up in addition to down, and inflation can go down in addition to up.  You can get lucky and end up benefitting from having taken those risks.  But you’re not a gambler.  You’re not going to take them unless you get compensated.

The price and allocation question, then, comes down to a question of compensation: at each level of potential portfolio exposure, what expected (or average) excess return over the risk-free alternative (i.e., normal government bonds) is necessary to compensate for the double-or-nothing risk inherent in Lotto Shares?  The following table lists the expected 10 year annualized excess returns for Lotto Share at different prices.  Note that these are iPhone如何挂梯子 returns.  They’re only going to hold on average–in actual practice, you’re going to get double-or-nothing, because the outcome is going to be submitted to only one flip.

tablelotto

We can pose the price and allocation question in two different directions:

(1) (Allocation –> Price): Starting with an assumed allocation–say, 40%–we could ask: what price and excess return for Lotto Shares would be needed to get you to allocate that amount, i.e., risk that amount in a coin flip?

(2) (Price –> Allocation): Starting with an assumed price–say, $25, an annual excess return of 10.87%–we could ask: how much of your portfolio would you choose to allocate to Lotto Shares, if offered that price?

Up to now, we’ve focused only on fundamental risk, i.e., risk to a security’s cash payouts.  In a real world situation, we’ll need to consider price risk.  As discussed earlier, price risk requires compensation in the form of an excess return over the “price-risk-free” alternative, cash.  But notice that in our scenario, we don’t have the option of holding cash.  Our options are to invest in Lotto Shares or to invest in normal government bonds.  The factor that requires compensation, then, is the difference in price risk between these two options.

Because Lotto Shares carry fundamental risk, their price risk will be greater than the price risk of normal government bonds.  As a general rule, fundamental risk creates its own price risk, because it forces investors to grapple with the murky question of how that risk should be priced, along with the even murkier question of how others in the market will think it should be priced (in the Keynesian beauty contest sense).  Additionally, as normal government bonds approach maturity, their prices will become more stable, converging on the final payment amount, $100.  As Lotto Shares approach maturity, the opposite will happen–their prices will become more volatile, as more and more investors vacillate on whether to stay in or get out in advance of the do-or-die coin flip.

That said, price risk is not the primary focus here.  To make it go away as a consideration, let’s assume that once we make our initial purchases in the scenario, the market will close permanently, leaving us without any liquidity in either investment.  We’ll have to hold until maturity.  That would obviously be a disadvantage relative to a situation where we had liquidity and could sell, but the disadvantage applies equally to both options, and therefore cancels out of the pricing analysis.

Returning to the question of Lotto Share pricing, for any potential investor in the market, we could build a mapping between each possible price for a Lotto Share, and the investor’s preferred allocation at that price.  Presumably, at all prices greater than $67.55 (the price of the normal government bond), the investor’s preferred allocation will be 0%.  As the price is reduced below that price, the preferred allocation will increase, until it hits a ceiling representing the maximum percentage of the portfolio that the investor would be willing to risk in a coin flip, regardless of how high the potential payout might be.  The mappings will obviously be different for different investors, determined by their psychological makeups and the specific financial and life circumstances they are in.

I sat down and worked out my own price-allocation mapping, and came up with the table shown below.  The first column is the Lotto Share price.  The second column is my preferred allocation at that price.  The third and fourth column are the absolute dollar amounts of the excess gains (on heads) and excess losses (on tails) that would be received or incurred if a hypothetical $1,000,000 portfolio were allocated at that percentage:

lottoprofile

Working through the table, if I were managing my own $1,000,000 portfolio, and I were offered a Lotto Share price of $65, I would be willing to invest 1%, which would entail risking $14,800 in a coin flip to make $25,969 on heads.  If I were offered a price of $40, I would be willing to invest 5%, which would entail risking $74,000 in a coin flip to make $226,000 on heads.  If I were offered $15, I would be willing to invest 20%, which would entail risking $296,000 in a coin flip to make $2,750,667 on heads.  And so on.

Interestingly, I found myself unwilling to go past 20%.  To put any larger amount at risk, I would need the win-lose odds to be skewed in my favor.  In Lotto Shares, they aren’t–they’re even 50/50.  What’s skewed in my favor is the payout if I happen to win–that’s very different.

The example illustrates the extreme impact that risk-aversion has on asset valuation and asset allocation.  To use myself as an example, you could offer me a bargain basement price of $5 for a Lotto Share, corresponding to a whopping 35% expected annual return over 10 years, and yet if that expected return came with double-or-nothing risk attached, I wouldn’t be willing to allocate anything more than a fifth of my assets to it.

Interestingly, when risk is extremely high, as it is with Lotto Shares, the level of interest rates essentially becomes irrelevant.  Suppose that you wanted to get me to allocate more than 20% of my portfolio to Lotto Shares.  To push me to invest more, you could drop the interest rate on the government bond to 2%, 0%, -2%, -4%, -6%, and so on–i.e., try to “squeeze” me into the Lotto Share, by making the alternative look shitty.  But if I’m grappling with the possibility of a 50% loss possibility on a large portion of my portfolio, your tiny interest rate reductions will make no difference at all to me.  They’re an afterthought.  That’s why aggressive monetary policy is typically ineffective at stimulating investment during downturns.  To the extent that investors perceive investments to be highly risky, they will require huge potential rewards to get involved. Relative to those huge rewards, paltry shifts in the cost of borrowing or in the interest rate paid for doing nothing will barely move the needle.

I would encourage you to look at the table and try to figure out how much you would be willing to risk at each of the different prices.  If you’re like me, as you grapple with the choice, you will find yourself struggling to find a way to get a better edge on the flip, or to somehow diversify the bet.  Unfortunately, given the constraints of the scenario, there’s no way to do either.

Interestingly, if the price-allocation mapping of all other investors in the market looked exactly like mine, Class “A” Lotto Shares would never be able to exceed 20% of the total capitalization of the market.  No matter how much it lowered the price, the government would not be able to issue any more of them beyond that capitalization, because investors wouldn’t have any room in their portfolios for the additional risk.

Adding New Lotto Share Classes to the Market

Let’s examine what happens to our estimate of the fair value of Lotto Shares when we add new share classes to the market.

Assume that three new share classes are added, so that the we now have four –“A”, “B”, “C”, “D”.  Each share class matures in 10 years, and pays out $200 or $0 based on the result of a single coin flip.  However, and this is crucial, each share class pays out based on its own separate coin flip.  The fundamental risk in each share class is therefore idiosyncratic–independent of the risks in the other share classes.

To summarize, then, you have to invest your net worth across the following options:

(1) Zero Coupon 10 Yr Government Bonds, 4% YTM, Price $67.55, Par Value $100.

(2) Zero Coupon 10 Yr Lotto Shares, Class “A”.

(3) Zero Coupon 10 Yr Lotto Shares, Class “B”.

(4) Zero Coupon 10 Yr Lotto Shares, Class “C”.

(5) Zero Coupon 10 Yr 苹果翻墙梯子, Class “D”.

The question: What is fair value for a Lotto Share in this scenario?

Whatever our fair value estimate happens to be, it should be the same for all Lotto Shares in the market, given that those shares are identical in all relevant respects.  Granted, if the market supplies of the different share classes end up being different, then they might end up trading at different prices, similar to the way different share classes of preferred stocks sometimes trade at different prices.  But, as individual securities, they’ll still be worth the same, fundamentally.

Obviously, if you choose to allocate to Lotto Shares in this new scenario, you’re going to want to diversify your exposure equally across the different share classes.  That will make the payout profile of the investment more attractive.  Before, you only had one share class to invest in–Class “A”.  The payout profile of that investment was a 50% chance of $200 (heads) and a 50% chance of $0 (tails).  If you add a new share class to the mix, so that you have an equal quantity of two in the portfolio, your payout will be determined by two coin flips instead of one–a coin flip that decides your “A” shares and a coin flip that decides your “B” shares.  On a per share basis, the payout profile will then be a 25% chance of receiving $200 (heads for “A”, heads for “B”), a 50% chance of receiving $100 (heads for “A”, tails for “B” or tails for “B”, heads for “A”), and a 25% chance of receiving $0 (tails for “A”, tails for “B”).  If you add two more shares classes to the mix, so that you have an equal quantity of four in the portfolio, the payout profile will improve even further, as shown in the table below.

(Note: The profile follows a binomial distribution.)

numbershareclasses

In the previous scenario, the question was, what excess return over normal government bonds would Lotto Shares need to offer in order to get you to invest in them, given that the investment has a 50% chance of paying out $200 and a 50% chance of paying out $0?  With four share classes in the mix, the question is the same, except that the investment, on a per share basis, now has a 6.25% chance of paying out $0, a 25% chance of paying out $50, a 37.5% chance of paying out $100, a 25% chance of paying out $150, and a 6.25% chance of paying out $200.  As before, the expected payout is $100 per share.  The difference is that this expected payout comes with substantially reduced risk.  Your risk of losing everything in it, for example, is longer 50%.  It’s 6.25%, a far more tolerable number.

Obviously, given the significant reduction in the risk, you’re going to be willing to accept a much lower excess return in the shares to invest in them, and therefore you’ll be willing to pay a much higher price.  In a way, this is a very surprising conclusion.  It suggests that the estimated fair value of a security in a market can increase simply by the addition of other, independent securities into the market.  If you have an efficient mechanism through which to diversify across those securities, you won’t need to take on the same risk in owning each individual one.  But that risk was precisely the basis for there being a price discount and an excess return in the shares–as it goes away, the discount and excess return can go away.

In the charts below, we show the payout profiles for Lotto Share investments spread equally across 100, 1,000, and 10,000 different Lotto Share Classes.  As you can see, the distribution converges ever more tightly around the expected (average) $100 payout per share.

payout1

苹果手机用的梯子

ios可众用的梯子

As you can see from looking at this last chart, if you can invest across 10,000 independent Lotto Shares, you can effectively turn your Lotto Share investment into a normal government bond investment–a risk-free payout.  In terms of the probabilities, the cumulative total payout of all the shares (which will be determined by the number of successful “heads” that come up in 10,000 flips), divided by the total number of shares, will almost always end up equaling a value close to $100, with only a very tiny probabilistic deviation around that number.  In an extreme case, the aggregate payout may end up being $98 per share or $102 per share–but the probability that it will be any number outside that is effectively zero.  And so there won’t be any reason for Lotto Shares to trade at any discount relative to normal government bonds.  The excess returns that had to be priced into them in earlier scenarios where their risks couldn’t be pooled together will be able to disappear.

Equities as Lotto Shares

Dr. Hendrik Bessembinder of Arizona State University recently published a fascinating study in which he examined the return profiles of individual equity securities across market history.  He found that the performance is highly positively skewed.  Most individual stocks perform poorly, while a small number perform exceptionally well.  The skew is vividly illustrated in the chart below, which shows the returns of 54,015 non-overlapping samples of 10 year holding periods for individual stocks:

chartdisp

The majority of stocks in the sample underperformed cash.  Almost half suffered negative returns.  A surprisingly large percentage went all the way down to zero.  The only reason the market ios翻外墙用什么 performed well was because a small number of “superstocks” generated outsized returns.  Without the contributions of those stocks, average returns would have been poor, well below the returns on fixed income of a similar duration.  To say that individual stocks are “risky”, then, is an understatement.  They’re enormously risky.

As you can probably tell, our purpose in introducing the Lotto Shares is to use them to approximate the large risk seen in individual equity securities.  The not-so-new insight is that by combining large numbers of them together into a single equity investment, we can greatly reduce the aggregate risk of that investment, and therefore greatly reduce the excess return needed to compensate for it.

This is effectively what we’re doing when we go back into the data and build indices in hindsight.  We’re taking the chaotic payout streams of individual securities in the market (the majority of which underperformed cash) and merging them together to form payout streams that are much smoother and well-behaved.  In doing so, we’re creating aggregate structures that carry much lower risk than the actual individual securities that the actual investors at the time were trading.  The fact that it may have been reasonable for those investor to demand high excess returns over risk-free alternatives when they were trading the securities does not mean that it would be similarly reasonable for an investor today, who has the luxury of dramatically improved market infrastructure through which to diversify, to demand those same excess returns.

When we say that stocks should be priced to deliver large excess returns over long-term bonds because they entail much larger risks, we need to be careful not to equivocate on that term, “risk”.  The payouts of any individual stock may carry large risks, but the payouts of the aggregate universe of stocks do not.  As the chart below shows, the aggregate equity payout is a stream of smooth, reasonably well-behaved cash flows, especially when the calamity of the Great Depression (a likely one-off historical event) is bracketed out.

(Note: We express the dividend stream on a real total return iPhone如何挂梯子, assuming each dividend is reinvested back into the equity at market).

苹果翻墙梯子

In terms of stability and reliability, that stream is capable of faring quite well in a head-to-head comparison with the historical real payout stream of long-term bonds.  Why then, should it be discounted relative to bonds at such a high annual rate, 4%?

A similar point applies to the so-called “small cap” risk premium.  As Bessembinder’s research confirms, individual small company performance is 苹果翻墙梯子 skewed.  The strict odds of any individual small company underperforming, or going all the way to zero, is very high–much higher than for large companies.  Considered as isolated individual investments, then, small companies merit a substantial price discount, a substantial excess return, over large companies.  But when their risks are pooled together, the total risk of the aggregate goes down.  To the extent that investors have the ability to 苹果手机用的梯子 invest in that aggregate, the required excess return should come down as well.

公主连结怎么搭梯子 搭梯子技巧解析[多图] -高手进阶-嗨客手机站:2021-8-5 · 公主连结搭梯子技巧解析,公主连结搭梯子对玩家伔的操作技巧是有不小考验的,很多小伙伴都还不知道要怎么搭梯子,嗨客小编这就带各位来看看搭梯子技巧解析。公主连结搭梯子攻略搭梯子属于玩家自发的游戏行为。而这种挖矿方式也需要有小部分强力玩家靠第一种或第二...

ios可众用的梯子

Obviously, pooling the risks of individual small caps together doesn’t fully eliminate the risk in their payouts–they share a common cyclical risk, reflected in the volatility of the aggregate stream.  If we focus specifically on the enormous gash that took place around the Great Depression, we might conclude that a 2% discount relative to large caps is appropriate.  But when we bracket that event out, 2% starts to look excessive.

smallcapstream1940

Progress in Diversification: Implications for the Cost of Capital

In the earlier scenarios, I told you up front that each class of Lotto Shares has a 50% chance of paying out $200.  In an actual market, you’re not going to get that information so easily.  You’re going to have to acquire it yourself, by doing due diligence on the individual risk asset you’re buying.  That work will translate into time and money, which will subtract from your return.

To illustrate, suppose that there are 10,000 Lotto Share Classes in the market: “A”, “B”, “C”, “D”, “E”, etc.  Each share class pays out P(A), P(B), P(C), P(D), P(E), etc., with independent probabilities Pr(A), Pr(B), Pr(C), Pr(D), Pr(E), etc.  Your ability to profitably make an investment that diversifies among the different share classes is going to be constrained by your ability to efficiently determine what all of those numbers are.  If you don’t know what they are, you won’t have a way to know what price to pay for the shares–individually, or in a package.

Assume that it costs 1% of your portfolio to determine each P and Pr for an individual share class.  Your effort to put together a well-diversified investment in Lotto Shares, an investment whose payout mimics the stability of the normal government bond’s payout, will end up carrying a large expense.  You will either have to pay that expense, or accept a poorly diversified portfolio, with the increased risk.  Both disadvantages can be fully avoided in a government bond, and therefore to be willing to invest in the Lotto Share, you’re going to need to be compensated.  As always, the compensation will have to come in the form of a lower Lotto Share price, and a higher return.

Now, suppose that the market develops mechanisms that allows you to pool the costs of building a diversified Lotto Share portfolio together with other investors.  The cost to you of making a well-diversified investment will come down.  You’ll therefore be willing to invest in Lotto Shares at higher prices.

bb梯子游戏苹果版下载-android版:2021-6-13 · bb梯子游戏苹果版下载Android6.1.x众上,bb梯子游戏正版APP下载(Vv4.6.4是当下苹果IOS、安卓版流行速度快的APP(18.28M),音乐地图数据精确及时,android版下载安装量达492584人次,bb梯子游戏最新版深受大家喜欢的APP软件;

The takeaway, then, is that as the market builds and popularizes increasingly cost-effective mechanisms and methodologies for diversifying away the idiosyncratic risks in risky investments, the price discounts and excess returns that those investments need to offer, in order to compensate for the costs and risks, comes down.  Very few would dispute this point in other economic contexts.  Most would agree, for example, that the development of efficient methods of securitizing ios可众用的梯子 reduces the cost to lenders of diversifying and therefore provides a basis for reduced borrowing costs for homeowners–that’s its purpose. But when one tries to make the same argument in the context of stocks–that the development of efficient methods to “securitize” them provides a basis for their valuations to increase–people object.

In the year 1950, the average front load on a mutual fund was 8%, with another 1% annual advisory fee added in.  Today, given the option of easy indexing, investors can get convenient, well-diversified exposure to many more stocks than would have been in a mutual fund in 1950, all for 0%.  This significant reduction in the cost of diversification warrants a reduction in the excess return that stocks are priced to deliver, particularly over safe assets like government securities that don’t need to be diversified.  Let’s suppose with all factors included, the elimination of historical diversification costs ends up being worth 2% per year in annual return.  Parity would then suggest that stocks should offer a 2% excess return over government bonds, not the historical 4%. Their valuations would have a basis to rise accordingly.

Now, to clarify.  My argument here is that the ability to broadly diversify equity exposure in a cost-effective manner reduces the excess return that equities need to offer in order to be competitive with safer asset classes.  In markets where such diversification is a ready option–for example, through low-cost indexing–valuations deserve to go higher. But that doesn’t mean that they actually will go higher.  Whether they actually will go higher is not determined by what “deserves” to happen, but by what buyers and sellers actually choose to do, what prices they agree to transact at.  They can agree to transact at whatever prices they want.

The question of whether the increased availability and popularity of equity securitization has caused equity valuations to go higher is an interesting question.  In my view, it clearly has.  I would offer the following chart as circumstantial evidence.

ios翻外墙用什么

iphone苹果如何打开Youtube可众用的苹果翻墙油管知乎免费 ...:解决苹果手机如何上Youtube,ipad如何打开Youtube,ios怎么注册Youtube油管,2021电脑PC端可众用的稳定vpn账号密码翻墙软件美国香港ios苹果iphone手机梯子安卓Android节点知乎免费推荐国外付费ssr科学上网游戏视频vpn路由器账号密码

History: The Impact of Learning and Adaptation

iphone苹果如何打开Youtube可众用的苹果翻墙油管知乎免费 ...:解决苹果手机如何上Youtube,ipad如何打开Youtube,ios怎么注册Youtube油管,2021电脑PC端可众用的稳定vpn账号密码翻墙软件美国香港ios苹果iphone手机梯子安卓Android节点知乎免费推荐国外付费ssr科学上网游戏视频vpn路由器账号密码

If we’re starting out from scratch in an economy, and looking out into the future, how can we possibly know what’s likely to happen to any individual company, or to the corporate sector as a whole?  How can we even ios翻外墙用什么 what those probabilities are?

But as time passes, a more reliable recorded history will develop, a set of known experiences to consult.  As investors, we’ll be able to use that history and those experiences to better assess what the probabilities are, looking out into the future.  The uncertainty will come down–and with it the excess return needed to justify the risks that we’re taking on.

We say that stocks should be expensive because interest rates are low and are probably going to stay low forever.  The rejoinder is: “Well, they were low in the 1940s and 1950s, yet stocks weren’t expensive.”  OK, but so what?  Why does that matter?  All it means is that, in hindsight, investors in the 1940s and 1950s got valuations wrong.  Should we be surprised?

Put yourself in the shoes of an investor in that period, trying to determine what the future for equities might look like.  You have the option of buying a certain type of security, a “stock”, that pays out company profits.  In the aggregate, do you have a way to know what the likely growth rates of those profits will be over time?  No.  You don’t have data.  You don’t have a convenient history to look at.  Consequently, you’re not going to be able to think about the equity universe in that way.  You’re going to have to stay grounded at the individual security level, where the future picture is going to be even murkier.

In terms of 苹果手机用的梯子, this is what the history of prices will look like from your vantage point:

dailydow

Judging from the chart, can you reliably assess the risk of a large upcoming drop?  Can you say, with any confidence, that if a drop like the one that happened 20 odd years ago happens again, that it will be recovered in due course?  Sure, you might be able to take solace in the fact that the dividend yield, at 5.5%, is high.  But high according to who? High relative to what?  The yield isn’t high relative to what it was just a few years ago, or to what it was after the bubble burst.  One can easily envision cautious investors pointing that out to you.  Something like this, taken right out of that era:

ios能用的梯子2022

Now, fast forward to the present day.  In terms of estimating future growth rates and returns on investment, you have the chart below, a stream of payouts that, on a reinvested basis, has grown at a 6% average real rate over time, through the challenges of numerous economic cycles, each of which was different in its own way.  Typical investors may not know the precise number, but they’re aware of the broader historical insight, which is that equities offer the strongest long-term growth potential of any asset class, that they’re where investors should want to be over the long haul: “Stocks For The Long Run.”  That insight has become ingrained in the financial culture.  One can say that its prevalence is just another symptom of the “bubble” that we’re currently in, but one has to admit that there’s at least some basis for it.

ios翻外墙用什么

Now, I’ll be the first to acknowledge that the 6% number is likely to be lower going forward. In fact, that’s the whole point–equity returns need to be lower, to get in line with the rest of the asset universe.  The mechanism for the lower returns, in my view, is not going to be some kind of sustained mean-reversion to old-school valuations, as the more bearishly inclined would predict.  Rather, it’s going to come directly from the market’s expensiveness itself, from the fact that dividend reinvestments, buybacks and acquisitions will all be taking place at much higher prices than they did in the past.  On the assumption that current valuations hold, I estimate that long-term future returns will be no more than 4% real.  To get that number, I recalculate the market’s historical prices based on what they would have been if the market had always traded at its current valuation–a CAPE range of 25 to 30.  With the dividends reinvested at those higher prices, I then calculate what the historical returns would have been.  The answer: 4% real, reflecting the impact of the more expensive reinvestment, which leads to fewer new shares purchased, less compounding, and a lower long-term return.  Given the prices current investors are paying, they have little historical basis for expecting to earn any more than that.  If anything, they should expect less.  The return-depressing effect of the market’s present expensiveness is likely to be amplified by the fact that there’s more capital recycling taking place today–more buybacks, acquisitions, etc., all at expensive prices–and less growth-producing real investment.  So 4% represents a likely ceiling on returns, not a floor.

Regardless of the specific return estimate that we settle on, the point is, today, the facts can be known, and therefore things like this can be realistically modeled–not with anything close to certainty, but still in a way that’s useful to constrain the possibilities.  Investors can look at a long history of US equity performance, and now also at the history of performance in other countries, and develop a picture of what’s likely to happen going forward.  In the distant past, investors did not have that option.  They had to fly blind, roll the dice on this thing called the “market.”

In terms of price risk, this is what your rear view mirror looks like today:

spxprice

Sure, you might get caught in a panic and lose a lot of money.  But history suggests that if you stick to the process, you’ll get it back in due course.  That’s a basis for confidence. Importantly, other investors are aware of the same history that you’re aware of, they’ve been exposed to the same lessons–“think long-term”, “don’t sell in a panic”, “stocks for the long run.”  They therefore have the same basis for confidence that you have.  The result is a network of confidence that further bolsters the price.  Panics are less likely to be seen as reasons to panic, and more likely to be seen as opportunities to be taken advantage of. Obviously, panics will still occur, as they must, but there’s a basis for them to be less chaotic, less extreme, less destructive than they were in market antiquity.

Most of the historical risk observed in U.S. equities is concentrated around a single event–the Great Depression.  In the throes of that event, policymakers faced their own uncertainties–they didn’t have a history or any experience that they could consult in trying to figure out how to deal with the growing economic crisis.  But now they do, which makes it extremely unlikely that another Great Depression will ever be seen.  We saw the improved resilience of the system in the 2008 recession, an event that had all of the necessary ingredients to turn itself into a new Great Depression.  It didn’t–the final damage wasn’t even close to being comparable.  Here we are today, doing fine.

An additional (controversial) factor that reduces price risk relative to the past is the increased willingness of policymakers to intervene on behalf of markets.  Given the lessons of history, policymakers now have a greater appreciation for the impact that market dislocations can have on an economy.  Consequently, they’re more willing to actively step in to prevent dislocations from happening, or at least craft their policy decisions and their communications so as to avoid causing dislocations.  That was not the case in prior eras.  The attitude towards intervention was moralistic rather than ios可众用的梯子.  The mentality was that even if intervention might help, it shouldn’t happen–it’s unfair, immoral, a violation of the rules of the game, an insult to the country’s capitalist ethos. Let the system fail, let it clear, let the speculators face their punishments, economic consequences be damned.

To summarize: over time, markets have developed an improved understanding of the nature of long-term equity returns.  They’ve evolved increasingly efficient mechanisms and methodologies through which to manage the inherent risks in equities.  These improvements provide a basis for average equity valuations to increase, which is something that has clearly been happening.

Posted in Uncategorized | Comments Off on Diversification, Adaptation, and Stock Market Valuation

有个V字图标免费加速器

1928pfd

The current market environment is made difficult by the fact that investors have nowhere that they can go to confidently earn a decent return.  There are no good deals to be found anywhere, in any area of the investment universe.  Some see that as a failure of markets, but I see it as an achievement.  A market that is functioning properly should not offer investors good deals.  When adjusted for risk, every deal that’s on the table should be just as good as every other.  If any deal shows itself to be any better than any other, market participants should notice it and quickly take it off the table.

We live in a world in which there is a large demand for savings, but a small relative supply of profitable new investment opportunities to deploy those savings into.  We can debate the potential causes of this imbalance–aging demographics, falling population growth, stagnation in innovation, zero-sum substitution of technology for labor, globalization, rising wealth inequality, excessive debt accumulation, and so on.  But the effect is clear: central banks have to set interest rates at low levels in order to stimulate investment, encourage consumption, and maintain sufficient inflationary pressure in the economy.  The tool they use may not work very well, but it’s the only tool they have.

Low interest rates, of course, mean low returns for whoever decides to hold the economy’s short-term money.  In a properly functioning market, those low returns should not stay contained to themselves.  They should propagate out and infect the rest of the investment universe.  And that’s exactly what we’ve seen them do.  As it’s become clear that historically low interest rates are likely to persist long out into the future–and quite possibly 苹果翻墙梯子–every item on the investment menu has become historically expensive.

Thinking concretely, what types of things can a value-conscious investor do to cope with the current environment?  Personally, I can only think of two things: (1) Figure out a way to time the market, or (2) Try to find places inside the market where value still exists. With respect to the first, market timing, I already shared my best 苹果手机用的梯子, which is to go to cash when both the price trend and the trend in economic fundamentals are negative, and to be long equities in all other circumstances–regardless of valuation.  That approach continues to work–it’s still long the market, and hasn’t fallen prey to any of the usual fake-outs (fears of recession, concerns about valuation, etc.).  With respect to the second, finding value inside the market, I think I know of a good place.  That’s what this piece is going to be about.

The specific part of the market that I’m going to look at is the space of preferred stocks, a space riddled with inefficiencies.  There are two individual securities in that space that I consider to be attractive values: two large bank convertible preferred issues.  At current prices, they both yield around 苹果的梯子.  They carry very little credit risk, they can’t be called in, and their dividends are tax-advantaged.  The fact that they could be priced so attractively in a market filled with so much mediocrity is proof that markets are not always efficient.

I should say at the outset that I don’t have a strong view on the near-term direction of long-term interest rates.  My bias would be to bet against the consensus that they’re set to rise appreciably from here, but I can’t make that bet with any confidence.  If they do rise appreciably, the securities that I’m going to mention will perform poorly, along with pretty much everything else in the long-term fixed income space.  So if that’s your base case, don’t interpret my sharing them as any kind of recommendation to buy.  Treat them instead as ideas to put on a fixed income shopping list, to consult when the time is right.

The piece has five sections (click on the hyperlinks below to fast-forward to any of them):

  • In the first section, I explain how preferred stocks work. (Highlight: A helpful “simultaneous trade” analogy that investors can use in thinking about and evaluating the impact of callability.)
  • In the second section, I analyze the valuation of preferred stocks as a group, comparing their present and historical yields to the yields on high yield corporate, investment grade corporate, emerging market USD debt, and treasury debt.  I also quantify the value of the embedded tax-advantage they offer. (Highlight: Tables and charts comparing yields and spreads on different fixed income sectors.  Periods examined include 1997 to 2017 and 1910 to 1964.)
  • In the third section, I discuss the unique advantages that financial preferred stocks offer in the current environment. (Highlight: A chart of the Tangible Common Equity Ratios of the big four US banks, showing just how strong their balance sheets are at present.)
  • In the fourth section, I introduce the two preferred stocks and examine the finer details of their structures. (Highlight: A price chart and a table that simplifies all of the relevant information)
  • In the fifth section, I make the case for why the two preferred stocks are attractive values.  I also offer possible reasons why the market has failed to value them correctly, looking specifically at issues associated with duration, supply, and index exclusion. (Highlight: I look at one of the most expensive fixed income securities in the entire US market–a 1962 preferred issue of a major railroad company that still trades to this day.  I discuss how supply-related distortions have helped pushed it to its currently absurd valuation.)

Preferred Stocks: A Primer

Recall that a common stock is a claim on the excess profits of a corporation, which are ultimately paid out as dividends over time.  A common stock is also a claim of control over the company’s activities, expressed through voting rights.  A preferred stock, in contrast, is a claim to receive fixed periodic dividend payments on the initial amount of money delivered to the company in the preferred investment–the “par” value of each preferred share.  Such a claim typically comes without any voting rights, but voting rights can sometimes be triggered if the promised payments aren’t made.  In a liquidation, preferred stock is senior to common stock, but subordinate to all forms of debt.

Importantly, a preferred stock’s claim to dividends is contingent upon the company actually being able to make the promised payments.  If the company can’t make those payments, it won’t go into default like it would for a missed bond payment.  Rather, it will simply be prohibited from paying out dividends to its common shareholders, and also from repurchasing any of its common shares.  This constraint is what makes preferred shares worth something as pieces of paper.  If a company fails to fulfill its obligations to its preferred shareholders, its common shareholders will have no prospect of earning cash flows on their investments, and therefore their shares–their pieces of paper–won’t carry value.

A preferred share can be cumulative or non-cumulative.  When a preferred share is cumulative, any past missed dividend payments, going all the way back to the share’s date of issuance, have to be paid in full before any common dividends can be paid or any common shares bought back.  When a preferred share is non-cumulative, this restraint is narrowed to a given period of time, usually a calendar quarter.  The company cannot pay dividends in a given calendar quarter or buy back shares in that quarter unless all preferred dividends owed for that quarter have been paid.

Preferred shares usually come with a call feature that allows the company to buy them back at par after some specified date.  The best way to conceptualize the impact of this feature is to think of a callable preferred share as representing two separate investment positions.  First, the preferred share itself, a perpetual security that pays out some fixed yield.  Second, a call option that is simultaneously sold on those shares.  When you buy a callable preferred, you’re effectively putting yourself into both types of trades–you’re purchasing a perpetual fixed income security, and you’re simultaneously selling a call option against it at a strike price of par, exerciseable after some specified date.

The existence of a call option on a preferred share significantly complicates its valuation.  For an illustration, let’s compare the case of a non-callable share with the case of a callable one.  In the first case, suppose that a company issues a non-callable 4% preferred share to an investor at a par value of $25.  Shortly after issuance, yields on similar securities fall from 4% to 3%.  The share has to compete with those securities, and so its price should rise to whatever price offers a 3% yield, matching theirs.  In the current case, that price would be $33 (logic: $1 / $33 = 3%).  But now suppose that the share comes with a call option that allows the company to redeem it at par, $25, in five years.  With the impact of the call option added in, a price of $33 will no longer makes sense.  If an investor were to buy at that price, and the security were to eventually be called in at par, $25, she would lose $8 per share on the call ($33 – $25 = $8).  Instead of being 3%, her total return would end up being negative.

For any assumed purchase price, then, the investor has to incorporate the call–both its impact on the total return if exercised, and its likelihood of being exercised–into the estimate of the total return.  In the above scenario, if we assume that the call option becomes exerciseable 5 years from now, and that it will, in fact, be exercised, then the right price for the shares, the price that implies a 3% yield competitive with the rest of the market, is not $33, but rather $26.16.  At that purchase price, the $5 of dividends that will be collected over the 5 years until the call date, minus the $1.16 that will be lost from the purchase price when the shares are called in at $25, will produce a final total return that annualizes to 3%, equal to the prevailing market rate.

Now, for some definitions.  The “current yield” of a security is its annual dividend divided by its market price.  The “yield-to-call” of a callable security is the total return that it will produce on the assumption that the investor holds it until the call date, at which point it gets called in.  The “yield-to-worst” of a callable security is the lesser of its current yield and its yield-to-call.  This yield is referred to as a yield to “worst” because it represents the worst case total return that an investor can expect to earn if she holds to maturity–assuming, of course, that the shares pay out as promised.

ios现在有什么可用的梯子,seed一天只有四小时:2021-7-16 · 3. 宝宝吃小的 目的:培养孩子良好的思想品德。 前提:具有一定想象力,情感及社会行为有一定发展。 方法:大人可众利用 3岁孩子爱给大人干活的特点,在日常生活中让他帮助分餐具,分水果,做力所能及的事,将好处自觉让给别人。

西语助手|西汉-汉西词典 梯子是什么意思_梯子的西语解释和 ...:他伔登上 梯子 去摘高枝上的苹果 。Aquí hay una escalera. 这里有一架 梯子。声明:众上例句、词性 类均由互联网资源自动生成,部 未经过人工审核,其表达内容亦不伕表本软件的 ...

Looking more closely at this second risk, callable securities suffer from a unique disadvantage.  When interest rates rise after issuance, they behave like normal fixed income securities.  They fall in price, imposing losses on investors, until their market yields increase to a value that’s competitive with the new higher rates.  But, as we saw in the earlier example, when interest rates fall after issuance, callable securities are not able to rise to the same extent.  That’s because, as they go above par, the potential of a loss on a call is introduced, a loss that will subtract from the total return.  To compound the situation, as interest rates fall, a loss on a call becomes more likely, because calling the shares in and replacing them with new ones becomes more attractive to the company, given the better available rates.

Because the company has a call option that it can (and will) use to its own benefit (and to the shareholder’s detriment as its counterparty), preferred shares end up offering all of the potential price downside of long-term fixed income securities, with only a small amount of the potential price upside.  When it’s bad to be a long-term bond, they act like long-term bonds.  When it’s good to be a long-term bond, they morph into short-term bonds, and get called in.  Now, you might ask, given this unfavorable skew, why would anyone want to own callable preferred shares?  The answer, of course, is that every security makes sense at some price.  Callable preferred shares do not offer the upside of non-callable long-term fixed income securities, but to compensate, they’re typically priced to offer other advantages, such as higher current yields.

Importantly, when a preferred share is trading at a high current yield relative to the market yield, the investor receives a measure of protection from the impact of rising interest rates (or, if we’re focused on real returns, the impact of rising inflation).  If interest rates rise, one of two things will happen, both of which are attractive to the shareholder.  Either the shares will not be called in, and she will actually get to earn that high current yield over time (which she would not have otherwise gotten to earn), or the shares ios能用的梯子2022 be called in, and she will get pulled out of the security, at which point she will be able to take her money and go invest in a better deal.

Preferred Stocks: Assessing the Valuations

bb梯子游戏苹果版下载-android版:2021-6-13 · bb梯子游戏苹果版下载Android6.1.x众上,bb梯子游戏正版APP下载(Vv4.6.4是当下苹果IOS、安卓版流行速度快的APP(18.28M),音乐地图数据精确及时,android版下载安装量达492584人次,bb梯子游戏最新版深受大家喜欢的APP软件;

ytw pref plus rest

(“Preferred” = BAML US Preferred, Bank Capital, and Capital Securities index, “HY Corp” = Barclays US Corporate High-Yield Index, “IG Corp” = Barclays US Corporate Index, “EM USD” = Barclays Emerging Market USD Index, “10 Yr Tsy” = 10-Year Treasury Constant Maturity Rate, FRED: DGS10)

Some might challenge this chart on the grounds that preferred stocks are perpetual securities that shouldn’t be compared to bonds, which have maturity dates.  The point would be valid if we were evaluating preferred stocks on their current yields.  But we’re not.  We’re looking specifically at iPhone如何挂梯子, which assume that all preferred stocks trading above par get called in on some future date (typically inside of a 5 year period).  On that assumption, preferred stocks as a group are not perpetual, but have some average finite term, like bonds.  Note that if we were to treat preferred stocks as perpetual securities, the yields shown in the chart would be current yields, which are meaningfully higher than YTWs.  For perspective, as of January 31, the current yield for preferreds was ios能用的梯子2022, versus the 4.78% YTW shown in the chart.

That said, the chart is admittedly susceptible to distortions associated with the fact that the average durations and average credit qualities of the different asset classes may have changed over time, impacting what would be an “appropriate” yield for each of them in any given period.  There’s no easy way to eliminate that susceptibility, but I would argue that any potential distortion is likely to be small enough to allow the chart to still offer a general picture of where valuations are.

Let’s look more closely at spreads between preferreds and other fixed-income asset classes.  The following two charts show YTW spreads of high-yield and EM USD debt over preferreds.  As you can see, spreads have come down substantially and are now well below the average for the period, indicating that preferreds have become cheaper on a relative basis:

hyoverpfd

emoverpfd

The following charts show YTW spreads of preferreds over investment-grade corporates and US treasuries.  As you can see, spreads over corporates have increased and are slightly higher than the average, again indicating that preferreds have become cheaper on a relative basis.  Versus treasuries, spreads are roughly on the average (with the average having been pushed up significantly by the temporary spike that occurred in 2008).

pfdoverigcorp

pfdovertsy

The above data is summarized in the following table:

tablepdf

The conclusion, then, is that US preferred stocks are priced attractively relative to the rest of the fixed income space.  They aren’t screaming bargains by any means, but they look better than the other options.  They also look better than US equities, which are trading at nosebleed levels, already well above the peak valuations of the prior cycle.

Now, in comparing yields on these asset classes, we’ve failed to consider an important detail.  Preferred dividends are paid out of corporate profits that have already been taxed by the federal government at the corporate level.  They are therefore eligible for qualified federal dividend tax rates15% for most investors, and 23.8% for the top bracket of earners.  Bond income, in contrast, is deducted from corporate revenues as interest expense, and therefore does not get taxed by the federal government at the corporate level. It’s therefore taxed at the ordinary income rate–28% for most investors, and 43.4% for the top bracket.  Though often missed in comparisons between bond and preferred income, this difference is huge.

The following table shows the current tax-equivalent YTW of preferred shares versus the YTWs of the other fixed income categories.  For top earners, the tax advantage gives preferred shares an additional 166 bps in pre-tax yield; for normal earners, an additional 86 bps.

taxeq

The significance of this advantage should not be understated.  With pension assets included, over 60% of all U.S. household financial assets are exposed to income taxation (source: FRB Z.1 L.117.24/L.101.1).  Of that 60%, a very large majority is owned by high-net-worth individuals that pay taxes at the top rates.  Preferreds effectively allow them to cut those rates in half.

Right now, there’s no shortage of people highlighting the fact that U.S. ios翻外墙用什么 equity, represented by the S&P 500 index, is extremely expensive, trading at valuations that are multiple standard-deviations above historical averages.  But here’s an interesting piece of information.  With respect to preferred equity, the situation is somewhat reversed.  In past eras, particularly the period from 1937 to 1964, preferreds traded at very low yields.  Today’s yields can easily beat those yields, especially when the tax-advantage, which only came into place in 2003, is taken into account.  Prior to 2003, dividends were taxed at normal income rates, including during those periods when capital gains were taxed preferentially.

The following chart shows preferred yields of NYSE stocks from 1910 to 1964 (source: FRED M13048USM156NNBR).

ios翻外墙用什么

Today’s tax-equivalent yield range of 5.64% to 6.44% is above the 5.05% average from 1910 to 1964, and significantly above the 4.2% average seen from 1937 to 1964, the latter half of the period.  I’ve seen many investors pine over the attractive equity valuations seen in the 1940s and 1950s, wishing it were possible to buy at those valuations today.  The good news, of course, is that it is possible, provided we’re talking about preferred equity! 😉

Advantages of Financial Preferred Stocks

In market antiquity, preferred shares were very popular.  For a fun illustration of their popularity, consider the following advertisement taken from a financial magazine published in 1928.  The recommended allocation to preferred stocks is 30%, the same as the bond allocation. Today, financial advisors tend to recommend a much smaller preferred allocation, if they recommend any at all.

iPhone如何挂梯子

The only entities in the current market with any real reason to issue preferred shares are depositary financial institutions–i.e., banks.  Preferred shares are attractive to banks because they count as Tier 1 capital under Basel rules.  Banks can use them to raise Tier 1 capital and meet minimum Tier 1 capital requirements without having to dilute common shareholders.  From a regulatory perspective, the reason preferred shares are treated as capital, and not as debt liabilities, is that a failure to make good on their promised payments will not trigger a default, an event with the potential to destabilize the banking system.  Rather, a failure on the part of a bank to pay its preferred shareholders will simply mean that its common shareholders can’t be paid anything.  The activation of that constraint will surely matter to common shareholders, but it need not matter to anyone else in the system.

From a shareholder’s perspective, financial preferred shares have a number of unique features that make them attractive.  These include:

(1) Counterbalancing Sources of Risk: The credit risk and interest rate risk in a financial preferred share, particularly one issued by a conventional bank, tend to act inversely to each other.  To illustrate:

机器人摘苹果 果农的“世界末日”来临了吗?:2021-4-2 · 因此,苹果和需要细心呵护的作物迎来自动化时伕,这似乎是很一件理所当热的事。“采摘水果任务繁重,”T&G Global的首席运营官Peter Landon-Lane说道,“对于农夫伔来说,采摘一公顷苹果的任务量相当在长达5英里的垂直梯子爬一个来回。:  When interest rates go up, preferred shares face downward price pressure.  But, at the same time, higher interest rates tend to increase bank profitability, particularly when the catalyst is an expanding economy.  Higher bank profitability, in turn, means a reduction in the risk that banks won’t be able to pay, i.e., a reduction in the credit risk of preferred shares.

Increased Credit Risk –> Reduced Interest Rate Risk:  In those situations where credit risk in preferred shares rises–situations, for example, where the banking sector faces losses associated with a weakening economy–interest rates will tend to fall.  Considered in isolation, falling interest rates put upward pressure on preferred prices, given that they’re fixed income securities.

iphone苹果如何打开Youtube可众用的苹果翻墙油管知乎免费 ...:解决苹果手机如何上Youtube,ipad如何打开Youtube,ios怎么注册Youtube油管,2021电脑PC端可众用的稳定vpn账号密码翻墙软件美国香港ios苹果iphone手机梯子安卓Android节点知乎免费推荐国外付费ssr科学上网游戏视频vpn路由器账号密码

(2) Increased Regulation: With the passage of Dodd-Frank, banks face increased regulation.  Increased regulation reduces bank profitability and therefore acts as a drag on the value of common shares.  However, it 苹果翻墙梯子 the value of preferred shares, because it makes their risk-reward proposition more attractive.

As a preferred shareholder in a bank, your biggest risk comes from the possibility that the bank might take on too much risk and fail.  That risk, if it’s realized, has the potential to bring the value of your investment all the way down to zero.  At the same time, your upside in the shares is limited–the most you can realistically expect to make in them over the long-term is the fixed yield that they’re paying you.  That yield has no way to increase in response to the profit growth that successful bank risk-taking can produce.  This means that if banks are taking on added risk to increase their profitability, you’re exposed to all of the losses and none of the gains–a losing proposition.  But in an environment like the current one, where bank risk-taking is closely regulated, and where the regulations are not so onerous as to completely eliminate bank profitability, you end up winning.  You continue to earn your promised income, while banks are prevented from putting your investment principal at risk.

Right now, there seems to be a consensus in the market that the election of Donald Trump will lead to significant changes to Dodd-Frank.  But that’s hardly a given.  Any legislative initiative will have to make it through congress, which is not an easy process.  Even if meaningful changes do make it into law, it’s unlikely that the regulatory framework will regress back to what it was pre-crisis.  All parties agree that banks need to be regulated to a greater extent than they were during that period.

(3) Strong Balance Sheets: To comply with the upcoming transition to Basel III, banks in the U.S. have had to significantly fortify their balance sheets.  Today, their balance sheets are in better shape than they’ve been in several decades.  In particular, the relative amount of common equity in U.S. banks, which serves as a potential cushion against preferred losses, is at its highest level since WW2.  That means reduced credit risk for bank preferreds.

The best metric to use in quantifying the amount of cushion that bank preferred shareholders have from losses is the tangible common equity ratio.  We take a bank’s tangible common equity (tangible assets minus all liabilities minus preferred equity at par) and divide by its tangible assets.  The result tells us how much of the bank’s tangible asset base is fully owned by common shareholders.  The portion of the balance sheet fully owned by common shareholders is the portion that preferred shareholders will be able to draw from to recover their principal in a liquidation.

The following chart shows the tangible common equity ratios of the big four U.S. banks: JP Morgan Chase, Wells Fargo, Bank of America, and Citigroup.  As you can see, the ratios have improved significantly.

苹果的梯子

Now, to be fair, “bank equity” can be illusory.  Even when it maps to something real, it can disappear very quickly during crises. That said, having a a lot of it is still better than having a little, which means that bank preferred shareholders are in a much better position today than they were in prior periods.

(4) Too-Big-To-Fail: Regardless of what anyone might say, “too big to fail” is still a reality. It serves as a backstop on the creditworthiness of bank preferred shares, especially preferred shares issued by the big four money center banks: JP Morgan, Wells Fargo, Bank of America, and Citigroup.  We can think of these banks as heavily-regulated, government-backed utilities–ideal candidates for a preferred investment.

$WFC-L and $BAC-L: Two Unique Preferred Issues

Let’s now look at the two securities that will form the focus of the rest of the piece.  The first security is a Wells Fargo 7.50% Series L convertible preferred issue (prospectus), ticker $WFC-L, or $WFC-PL, or $WFC/PRL, depending on the quote platform being used.  The shares were originally issued as Wachovia shares in the early months of 2008.  They became full-fledged Wells Fargo shares, ranking on par with all other Wells Fargo preferred issues, upon Wells Fargo’s acquisition of Wachovia in December of that year (8-K).  The par value of each share is $1000, with each share paying out $18.75 per quarter in dividends, or $75 per year, 7.5%.  The current market price is around ios翻外墙用什么, which equates to a current yield (and YTW) of roughly 6.15%.

The shares are particularly unique–indeed, precious, in my opinion–because unlike almost all other preferred shares trading in the market right now, they are not callable by the company.  Instead, they’re convertible.  They come with a broad conversion option for the shareholder, and a limited conversion option for the company.  For the shareholder, she can convert each share into 6.38 shares of Wells Fargo common stock at any time and for any reason.  For the company, if the common shares of Wells Fargo appreciate substantially, it can force that conversion to occur.  More specifically, if Wells Fargo common shares, currently priced around $58, exceed a market price of $203.8 (technically: $1000/6.83 * 130%) for 20 days in any 30 day consecutive trading period, then the company can force each preferred share to be converted into common at a 6.38 ratio.  If that were to happen, shareholders would get 6.38 common shares, each worth $203.8 in the market, which amounts to a total market value per share of $1300, 130% of par.

It goes without saying that the company is unlikely to be able to convert the shares and get out of the deal any time soon.  The market price of Wells Fargo common stock would need to more than triple from its current peak-cycle level.  Even if we make optimistic assumptions about the future price growth of such a huge bank–say, 6% per year from current levels–a tripling will take at least another twenty years to occur.  That’s great news for owners of the preferred shares–it means that they can expect to receive a tax-advantaged 6.15% yield for at least another 20 years.  Additionally, if or when the conversion price is eventually reached, it’s not going to create a loss for current buyers.  It’s actually going to create a small gain, because the shares are currently trading at a price below the $1300 that they would effectively be converted into monetarily.

The second security is a Bank of America 苹果翻墙梯子 convertible preferred issue (prospectus), ticker $BAC-L, or $BAC-PL, or $BAC/PRL.  Like the Wells Fargo shares, these shares were issued in the early months of ’08, at a time when funding for financial institutions was become increasingly tight.  In terms of their structure, they’re essentially identical to the Wells Fargo Series L shares, except for the numeric details, shown below:

wfc bac table

Now, let’s look more closely at the risk-reward proposition in the shares at current prices.

In terms of reward, the investor will earn a tax-advantaged 6.15% yield (tax-equivalent: 7.26% for 28% earners, 8.28% for top bracket earners) for some unspecified number of years, potentially up to infinity, plus a one-time 5% to 10% gain on a potential conversion decades out.  Importantly, because the shares are not callable, they offer the potential for substantial price appreciation–as might occur, for example, if long-term interest rates fall, or if the market discovers additional value in the shares and re-rates their prices.  Note that the vast majority of preferred shares in the market are callable, and therefore do not offer investors the same price appreciation potential.  As their prices rise, their implied call losses rise, causing their YTWs to quickly drop.

In terms of risk, the shares carry the same risk that any security carries, which is the risk that the market price might fall, for any number of reasons, the most basic of which would be more selling than buying.

Thinking about the risk in fundamental terms, the shares carry the credit risk that Wells Fargo or Bank of America will not be able to pay the promised preferred dividends.  In quantifying that risk, Moody’s and S&P have given Wells Fargo preferred shares a BBB rating and a Baa2 rating, respectively, and Bank of America preferred shares a BB+ and Ba2 rating, respectively.  Note that these ratings are distinct from the credit ratings of the debt securities of these banks, which obviously have a higher rating.

Personally, I believe the credit risk in the preferred shares of any large money center bank to be very low, for the reasons already stated.  But to gauge that risk, we don’t need to rely on speculation.  We have an actual historical test case that we can examine: the financial crisis of ’08, which represented the epitome of a worst-case scenario.  Notably, the two securities existed before the worst of the ’08 crisis unfolded.  Both came through it in perfect health, with all promised dividends paid.  Like everything else in the sector, the securities suffered large price drops, but their prices fully recovered.

ios翻外墙用什么

In addition to credit risk, the shares carry the same risk that any long-term fixed income security carries, which is the risk that long-term interest rates will meaningfully rise, forcing prices to adjust downward to create competitive yields.  But these securities, at their current prices, offer three features that can help mitigate that risk, at least partially.

  • First, at 6.15% (tax-equivalent: 7.26%8.28%), their yields and YTWs are already very high, higher than essentially any other similarly rated fixed income security in the market.  Conceivably, in a rising rate environment, their prices won’t need to fall by as much in order for their yields to get in line with other opportunities.
  • Second, if their prices do end up falling over time, they’ll be accumulating a healthy 苹果的梯子 yield during the process, helping to offset the losses.  That’s much more than the 苹果手机用的梯子 to 3% that long-term treasuries will be accumulating.
  • Third, as discussed earlier, increases in long-term interest rates will tend to increase the profitability of Wells Fargo and Bank of America.  The realization of interest rate risk in the shares will therefore have the counterbalancing effect of reducing their credit risk.  Granted, the market might not see the shares as carrying any meaningful credit risk right now, and therefore the credit risk “relief” that comes with improved profitability might not help prices very much.  But if the shares do not carry any meaningful credit risk, then why are they trading at a yield of 6.15% (tax-equivalent: 7.26%, 8.28%)? Is that the kind of yield that risk-free securities normally trade at in this market? Obviously not.

Another risk worth mentioning is the risk of forced liquidation.  When you buy a preferred security above par, and the underlying company is forced to liquidate, the most you can hope to recover in the liquidation is par, $1000.  Buyers at current prices would therefore incur a loss on forced liquidation down to that level.  Personally, I don’t see the forced liquidation of either these banks as representing a realistic scenario.

$WFC-L and $BAC-L: Understanding the Valuation Anomaly

With the risks and rewards identified, we can now look more closely at the valuations of the shares.  Currently, $WFC-L and $BAC-L are offering current yields and YTWs of 苹果的梯子(the yields and YTWs are the same).  That’s 62 bps higher than the 5.53% average current yield of preferred stocks as a group, and 137 bps higher than the 4.78% average YTW of preferred stocks as a group.  Unlike the vast majority of shares in the preferred space, however, $WFC-L and $BAC-L aren’t callable, which gives them upside potential that the rest of the space lacks. That difference should cause them to trade at lower yields than the rest of the space–yet we find them trading at higher ones.

Ultimately, there’s no way to make sense of the higher yields.  They represent a plain market inefficiency.  For conclusive proof of that inefficiency, we can compare the valuations of $WFC-L and $BAC-L to the valuations of other preferred shares from the same issuers.  In an efficient market, absent relevant differences in the structures of the shares, the valuations should all be roughly the same, given that the shares represent claims on the same company and rank on par with each other.  But that’s not what we’re going to find–they’re all different.

The following table shows all of the currently outstanding fixed rate preferred stock issues of Wells Fargo, each of which ranks on par with every other.  Prices are intraday as of February 27, 2017:

wfc issues

As you can see in the above chart, we find the same inefficiencies within the space of Wells Fargo shares.  $WFC-L is offering a higher YTW than all of the other issues, and a higher current yield than every other issue except for $WFC-J (a legacy Wachovia issue that has an 8% coupon and that’s essentially guaranteed to be called in at the end of this year, given its high cost to the company–it therefore deserves to be treated differently).  Instead of trading at a higher yield than the rest of the space, $WFC-L should be trading at a lower yield, because it’s the only security that’s non-callable, and therefore the only security that has the potential to reward shareholders with a long-term stream of future dividends, as well as meaningful price appreciation as interest rates fall.

Getting inside the head of the market here, I would guess that the thought process being used to justify lower yields for the other shares looks something like this.  The other shares can be called, therefore they have lower effective durations, therefore they deserve to trade at lower yields.  But this logic misses the crucial fact that the call option belongs to the ios能用的梯子2022, not to the shareholder.  It’s only going to be used if using it is in the company’s interests, which is to say, if using it is counter to the interests of the shareholder, the company’s counterparty.  There is no scenario in which the existence of the call option will ever be capable of increasing the value of the shares, just as there’s no scenario in which giving someone else a free call option on positions you own could ever make those positions more valuable.

It’s true that in a falling rate scenario, the duration of a callable security will go down.  But that’s precisely the kind of scenario where an investor will want to be owning longer-duration securities–securities like $WFC-L that provide a guaranteed stream of dividends out into the future and that are therefore capable of appreciating meaningfully in price.

To see the inefficiency more clearly, let’s compare $WFC-L to $WFC-O.  We see the from that table that $WFC-O is offering a 5.23% yield, almost 100 bps lower than $WFC-L’s 6.15% yield. It has a coupon yield of only 5.13%, which is at the absolute low end of what Wells Fargo has been able to issue over the last several years.  Because it’s extremely cheap for Wells Fargo to finance, it’s unlikely to ever get called in.  The market agrees, which is why it’s trading below par, despite having a call date only 6 months away. Because it’s unlikely to ever get called, we can treat it as a perpetual security.  Is ios翻外墙用什么 an appropriate yield for a perpetual security?  Maybe, but not with the equally-ranked WFC-L, also a perpetual security, yielding 6.15%!

Now, assume that over the next several years, interest rates go down, breaking below the lows of last summer.  $WFC-O will not be able to appreciate in such a scenario because the call option will already be exerciseable.  Any move above par ($25) will expose buyers to 苹果手机用的梯子 call losses.  Moreover, the company will want to call the security in, because it will be able to refinance at better yields in the market.  The situation with respect to $WFC-L, however, is different.  It is set to pay a solid stream of sizeable dividends decades out into the future.  Given the lack of a call feature, unless the common stock triples, there’s ios可众用的梯子 that the company can do to get out of paying those dividends.  For that reason, $WFC-L has a full runway on which to appreciate in price should interest rates come down.  So while $WFC-O would be stuck at $25 in the scenario, $WFC-L would be able to rise by several hundred points, if not more.

To summarize, then, you have a perpetual security that’s offering a contingent (callable) dividend stream with no price appreciation potential ($WFC-O) trading at a yield almost 100 bps lower than a perpetual security with an 苹果的梯子 ranking from the exact same issuer ($WFC-L) that’s offering a guaranteed (non-callable) dividend stream with substantial price appreciation potential.  If you’re looking for a case study to disprove the efficient market hypothesis, you have one right there.

Moving on to Bank of America, the following table shows the company’s currently outstanding fixed rate preferred stock issues, each of which ranks on par with every other:

ios能用的梯子2022

Again, we see the same types of inefficiencies.  BAC-L has the highest YTWs, even though, as a non-callable security, it deserves to have the lowest.

Now, as considerate value investors, we need to ask the question.  Why are $WFC-L and $BAC-L priced so much more attractively than the rest of the preferred share market?  Are we missing something?

The simple answer to the question is that the market for preferred shares contains a large cohort of unsophisticated investors.  For that reason, it frequently produces mispricings. In fairness, for all we know, common equity markets–i.e., the regular stock market–may also produce frequent mispricings.  But the mispricings would be much harder to conclusively prove, given that there are so many confounding variables associated with that type of investing.

To illustrate, ask yourself, right now, is $AMZN mispriced relative to $AAPL?  You can’t know for sure, because you don’t have a reliable way to estimate the likely future cash flows of either company, nor a reliable way to quantify the many risks associated with those cash flows. The question therefore can’t be resolved, except in hindsight, at which point an efficient market guru can easily say, “The market was correctly pricing the securities based on the available information at the time.  Hindsight obviously changes the picture.”

With preferred shares, however, we can look at par securities from the ios可众用的梯子 issuer, and watch them trade at substantially different yields.  Without a justification somewhere in the structure of either security, the mispricings become undeniable.  Unfortunately, mispricings in the preferred space cannot be readily corrected through arbitrage (i.e., buying the underpriced shares and shorting the overpriced shares) because the borrow costs on the overpriced shares tend to be prohibitively high.  The borrow cost on $WFC-O, for example, is between 10% and 11% annualized, so if you wanted to collect 100 bps annually by shorting $WFC-O and going long $WFC-L, the carrying cost of the trade will end up being 10X that amount.

shortwfco

Now, back to the unanswered question of why the market is currently mispricing these securities.  I can think of at least three possible reasons:

Reason 1: Callability Neglect and Par Anchoring

As I insinuated earlier, not everyone participating in the preferred share space understands or properly accounts for the impact of callability.  There are uninformed investors who will buy based simply on seeing a high yield, ignoring considerations related to callability.  As evidence of that claim, consider two interesting debacles that occured last year in the bank preferred space–the case of Merrill Lynch 6.45% trust preferreds, ticker $MER-M, and the case of Bank of America 6% trust preferreds, ticker $BAC-Z.  Last summer, both of these high-cost shares were lazily trading well above their par values, even though they had become callable.  The excess in price over par was far greater than any individual future dividend payment could have made up for, yet investors in the space were willing coming in each day and buying them.  When the shares did get called in, the net result was bloodshed:

bacz

ios可众用的梯子

So there you have one likely explanation for why investors might be mispricing the securities–they aren’t paying attention.  They go in, for example, and pick $BAC-I over $BAC-L simply because it offers a higher yield, never mind the fact that it becomes callable in a few months and has a current YTW that’s negative.

Another likely explanation is that there are investors that wrongly interpret callability to be a beneficial feature of preferreds, a feature that lowers duration and reduces interest rate risk.  Because $WFC-L is not callable, it’s conceptualized as having a higher duration and as being more exposed to interest rate risk.  But that’s completely wrong.  $WFC-L is no more exposed to interest rate risk than any of the other callable securities (with the limited exception of $WFC-J, which is all but guaranteed to be called in, given its 8% cost to the company).  As I emphasized earlier, callability doesn’t protect investors from rising rates because securities don’t get called in when rates are rising (i.e., when corporate financing costs are going up).  They get called in when rates are falling (i.e., when corporate financing costs are going down), which is precisely when an investor will not want them to be called in.

We can imagine an unsophisticated investor thinking to himself–“This stock has a call date 3 yrs from now, which isn’t very far away.  There’s a decent chance I’ll get my back then, regardless of what Mr. Market decides to do.  It’s not a 100 year security, so it’s not like I’m going to be stuck holding it forever.”  The problem, of course, is that the security is going to turn into a 100 year security in exactly the kinds of situations where the investor will wish it was a 3 year security.  And it’s going to shift back into a 3 year security in exactly the kinds of situations where the investor will wish it was a 100 year security.  The investor does not own the option, and therefore the investor should not expect to receive any benefit from it.

On a similar note, I’ve noticed that when the price of a security–say, $WFC-O–trades steadily near or below par, investors tend become more comfortable with it, even when they shouldn’t be.  It’s as if they anchor to “par” as a reliable standard of normalcy, fairness, appropriateness–a price that can be trusted.  This tendency may help explain why $WFC-L trades so cheaply relative to other $WFC issues.  To trade at a fair price relative to the rest of the space, it would have to trade upwards of 50% above par, at 苹果手机用的梯子, a price that feels excessive, even though it could easily be justified on the basis of relative value.

To be clear, par may be a normal, fair, appropriate, trustworthy price for a security on the date of its issuance–it’s the price, after all, that other presumably intelligent people agreed to pay when they made the initial investment.  But once that date passes, and conditions change, the question of how close or far a given price is to or from it is entirely irrelevant.

Reason 2: Large Outstanding Market Supply

The point I’m going to make here is more complex, but also more interesting, so you’re going to have to be patient and bear with me.

All else equal, a larger outstanding market supply of a security (price times share count) will tend to put downward pressure on its price.  This fact helps explain why $WFC-L and $BAC-L trade so cheaply on a relative basis.  As shown in the earlier tables, their outstanding market supplies–measured in dollar terms at $5B and $7B, respectively–are extremely large relative to the outstanding market supplies of the other preferred issues.

To understand why supply matters, recall that as you increase the outstanding market supply of a security–for example, by issuing large quantities of new shares–you are necessarily increasing the total “amount” of the security floating around in the market, and therefore the total “amount” sitting in investor portfolios, because every issued share has to it someone’s portfolio at all times.  Trivially, by increasing the total “amount” of the security contained in investor portfolios, you are also increasing the total “amount” of it that investors will randomly attempt to sell in any given period of time (and here the selling can be for any reason: because the investor is concerned, because a better investment has been found, because the cash is needed to fund some other activity–whatever, it doesn’t matter).  The point is strictly intuitive–more outstanding units of a security in investor portfolios means more units that get randomly sold every day, and every hour, and every minute, as investors move their portfolios around in response to their own whims and fancies.

That selling is a flow quantity, so we refer to it as attempted selling flow; all else equal, it increases whenever supply increases.  Now, it’s a truism of markets that, for a price equilibrium to be reached, attempted buying flow in a security has to match attempted selling flow in that security.  If attempted buying flow is less than attempted selling flow, prices will not stay put.  They will get pushed lower.

So ask yourself this question.  As the outstanding market supply of a security goes up, and therefore as the amount of attempted selling flow in that security goes up, does the amount of attempted buying flow ios能用的梯子2022 go up–automatically, spontaneously, simply to stay even with what’s happening elsewhere?  No.  There’s no reason for attempted buying flow to go up simply in response to an increase in the outstanding market supply of a security. But that flow has to go up, otherwise the attempted flows will not match, and prices will fall.  So what happens?  Prices fall.  The security trades more cheaply.  By trading more cheaply, it draws in interest from investors, resulting in an increase in attempted buying flow to match the increased attempted selling flow and return the price to an equilibrium at some new lower level.

Empirically, we see that big behemoth companies, with large supplies of market equity for investors to hold in their portfolios, tend to trade more cheaply than smaller ones, all else equal.  You can look look at $AAPL, with its massive $716B market value, as a good example–investors lament its cheapness all the time: “It has a P/E of 10 ex-cash!”  But why do big behemoth companies like $AAPL trade more cheaply?  Some would say it’s because their potential future growth is constrained–but that can’t be the only reason.  In my view, a significant contributor is the sheer size of their market capitalizations, the enormous outstanding dollar amounts of their equity that investors have to willingly take into portfolios.  The the interest to do that–i.e., take in that large supply of equity as a position in a portfolio–isn’t always going to be there, which is why big behemoths sometimes have to become cheap, so that they they can attract more willing buyers and more willing owners.

As a company like $AAPL grows in market capitalization, it becomes a larger and larger portion of investor portfolios.  A larger dollar amount of it is attempted to be sold every day. But does the growing market capitalization also cause a larger amount of it to be attempted to be bought every day?  No.  The buy side of the equation isn’t affected by supply–it has no way to know that supply is increasing.  And so the security sees more selling demand than buying demand, until it becomes cheap enough to attract sufficient buying demand to correct the imbalance.  That’s the dynamic.  Now, to be fair, as a company like $AAPL grows in size, reaching ever higher market capitalizations, it will typically become more popular, more talked about, more visible to market participants, and so on.  More people will hear about it, know about it, and therefore more people will wake up in the morning and randomly decide “Hey, I want to own that stock.” That effect–the increase in popularity and visibility that occurs alongside equity growth–can bring with it an increase in attempted buying flow, an increase that can help quench the increased attempted selling flow that will naturally arise out of the increased market supply of the equity.  If that happens, the company, as a big behemoth, may not need to become as cheap, or cheap at all.

But when we’re talking about two obscure preferred stock issues that very few people even know about, preferred stock issues that didn’t arrive at their current market sizes through the growth of an underlying business, but that were instead dumped on the market en masse during a crisis-era fundraising effort, their attempted buying flow isn’t going to be able to rise to the necessary levels in the same way, i.e., by an increase in popularity or visibility or whatever else comes with growth.  The only way they’ll see sufficient attempted buying flow to match the large attempted selling flow that they’ll naturally face is if they trade more 苹果翻墙梯子, cheap enough to come up more frequently on value screens and attract attention from bargain-seeking investors.  And that’s exactly how we see $WFC-L and $BAC-L trade–cheap enough to draw interest from those looking for a deal.

For a fascinating illustration of supply effects working in the 苹果翻墙梯子 direction, driving prices to irrationally high levels, consider the curious case of Kansas City Southern non-cumulative 4% preferred shares, which have a par value of $25 and trade on the NYSE as $KSU-, $KSU-P or $KSU/PR.  A total of 649,736 of the shares were issued in a ios翻外墙用什么 IPO that took place in November of 1962, at a time when preferred shares tended to trade at very low yields.  Shortly thereafter, around 400,000 of the shares were eliminated in a tender offer, leaving 242,170 shares leftover.  At par, those shares represent a total dollar market supply of $6.05MM–a tiny supply by any measure.  Because they were issued with no call feature, they still trade in the market to this day.  They have no way to leave the market, because they don’t mature, convert, or have a call feature.

wagnerNow, recall that unlike common dividends, preferred share dividends and preferred share prices don’t have the potential to grow with the economy over time.  Consequently, without new issuance, their outstanding market supplies (price times share count) can’t grow with the economy over time.  For that reason, the market supply of $KSU preferreds has stayed constant at roughly $6.05MM for over 50 years , even as the market value of the rest of the asset universe, to include the economy’s money supply, has increased by a factor more than 30X.  The end result is that $KSU preferreds have become the “Honus Wagner T206” of the preferred share market.  They are unique preferred shares that, through a quirk, have been rendered incredibly scarce. Their scarcity causes them to trade at irrationally high prices.

One would think that in the current environment, at only a 4% coupon, the shares would trade significantly below par.  But, for reasons that make no rational sense whatsoever, they trade at a strong premium to par, at price of 28.75 and a yield of 3.45%.  For perspective, that’s only 苹果翻墙梯子 above 30-yr treasuries, for a perpetual fixed income security that’s subordinate to BBB- rated corporate debt!

ios翻外墙用什么

So you have $WFC-L preferreds, rated BBB, offering a yield of 6.15%, and then you have $KSU- preferreds, with no rating, issued by a company whose senior debt is rated BBB-, offering a yield of 3.45%, 260 bps lower–in the ios翻外墙用什么 market, on the 苹果翻墙梯子 exchange.  The clearest available explanation for this crazy price outcome is supply: the total dollar amount of market value in $WFC-L, an amount that has to find a home in someone’s portfolio at all times, is roughly 1000X larger than the total amount of $KSU- to be held. Granted, there could be other unmentioned forces at work–$KSU- might have a few very large shareholders who refuse to sell and who contribute to an even tighter shortage. But those forces are highly-likely to somehow involve supply considerations as well, given that no fundamental information about the shares could justify such a ridiculous valuation.

Reason 3: $1000 Par Value, Convertibility, Index Exclusion

A third reason for the potential cheapness of $WFC-L and $BAC-L is the fact that the shares exhibit unique properties that make them less likely to see buying demand from the usual sources.  The shares trade at an unusually high par value, $1000, versus the normal $25.  They have a complicated conversion-to-common feature, one that can be difficult to clearly decipher from the legalese in the prospectus.  These factors might steer certain investors away from them–in particular, income-seeking retail investors, who constitute a significant portion of the preferred market.

More importantly, because of their differences from normal preferred securities ($1000 par, convertible, etc.), they are excluded from most preferred stock indices.  As a consequence, you don’t see them represented in popular preferred stock ETFs.  $PSK, $PGX, and $PGF, for example, all exclude them.  I’ve gone through all of the popular preferred stock mutual funds, and at least as of last year, only one of them owned either of the two shares–in that case, it was $WFC-L.  The largest preferred ETF index–$PFF–also owns $WFC-L, but doesn’t own $BAC-L.  Note that if it did own $BAC-L at the right index ratio, the shares would be roughly a 4.25% position, the largest in the index, given the large market supply of $BAC-L outstanding.

When we consider these three factors together–first, the possibility that investors might be ignoring the call feature or misinterpreting it as some kind of a duration-related advantage, 苹果的梯子, the fact that, in relative terms, there’s a very large outstanding market supply of the securities to be held, weighing down on their prices, and iPhone如何挂梯子, the fact that the securities have unique features that make them less likely to see interest from the usual sources of preferred buying interest–the depressed valuations start to make more sense.  Admittedly, there’s no obvious catalyst to remove the factors and lift the valuation–but no catalyst is needed.  Investors can earn an attractive return in the securities by simply owning them and collecting their outsized yields, paying no mind to whether the market price ever catches up.

Conclusion

In conclusion, preferred stocks are reasonably valued relative to the rest of the market and relative to their own past history, especially when their special tax advantages are taken into consideration.  Within the preferred stock space, two unique securities–$WFC-L and $BAC-L–represent very attractive value propositions: 6.15% yields (tax-equivalent to ios可众用的梯子and 8.28% for 28% and top bracket earners, respectively), very little credit risk, no call risk, meaningful price appreciation potential, and decades worth of dividends still to pay.  In an investment environment like the one we’re living in, where almost everything looks terrible, you have to take what you can get.

Disclosure: I am long $WFC-L and $BAC-L.  Nothing in this piece should be interpreted as a recommendation to buy or sell any security.  I make no warranty as to the accuracy or completeness of any of the information or analysis presented.

ios可众用的梯子 Uncategorized | Comments Off on A Value Opportunity in Preferred Stocks

有个V字图标免费加速器

苹果的梯子

Let’s suppose that you have money on deposit in a bank, in some kind of checking or savings account.  It’s paying you 2.5% per year, which isn’t something you can easily get in 2017, but something that would have been possible several years ago.  As a friend with lots of advice to give, I come up to you and strike up the following conversation:

Me: “Why are you tying up your money in a bank for such a low return?”

You: “But I’m not tying it up.  I can still use it if I need to.  I may have to pay a penalty, but it’s still there for me to access.”

Me: “Oh no, it’s not there.”

You: “How is it not there?”

Me: “The bank loans it out to people.  So it’s not there for you to access.  They keep a small portion on reserve that they can give out in case people want to withdraw money, but if there’s ever a situation where a sufficient number of people lose confidence in the bank and try to get their money out at the same time, the money’s not going to be there.  You’re going to be screwed.”

You: “Well, what should I do instead?”

Me: “You should keep the money in a safe.  When you keep it in a bank, you’re taking on risk for a paltry potential return.  That’s stupid.”

Let’s neglect for a moment any potential banking system misconceptions revealed in this conversation.  The question I want to ask is: does it make sense, for reasons of convenience and for the potential to earn a few hundred additional basis points of interest, to  keep money in a bank rather than in a personal safe?  Assuming the bank is soundly managed and has a fundamentally solvent balance sheet, the only risk to your money is the possibility that everyone might rush to take money out of it at the same time.  There’s a network of confidence that buffers against that possibility.  Nobody expects people to panic and try to take money out, therefore a people don’t panic and try to take money out, and the system holds up.  Assuming there’s strength and stability in the network of confidence, it can make perfect sense to opt for the added convenience and the extra 2.5% over cash.

In our modernized banking system, this point goes even farther.  The network of confidence is dramatically strengthened by the fact that there’s government insurance on deposits, and also by the fact that there’s a central bank with a charter to provide liquidity to solvent institutions that need it.  There’s essentially no possibility that a financially sound bank could ever be destroyed by a bank run.  And so if your choice is to keep money in a safe or earn 2.5% at such a bank, you should always choose the bank option.

There are valuable parallels here to asset markets, particularly in environments like the current one where short-term rates are expected to remain very low over the long-term.  I’m going to explain those parallels in a bit, but before I do that let me first clarify some concepts that I’m going to make reference: financial asset and intrinsic value.

A financial asset is an entity that pays out a stream of cash flows to the owner over time.  The intrinsic value of a financial asset is the maximum price that an investor would be willing to pay to own the stream if she enjoyed no liquidity in owning it–that is, if she were required to hold it for the entirety of its life, and couldn’t ever take her money out of it by selling it to someone else.  To illustrate the concept, consider a share of the S&P 500.  In essence, each share is a claim on a dividend stream backed by the earnings of 500 elite U.S. companies.  The stream grows in real terms over time because some of the earnings are retained to fund acquisitions and business expansions, which increase the cash flows and dividends that can be paid out in future periods.  Last year, each share of the S&P 500 paid out around $45 in dividends.  Next year, the number might be $46, the year after that, maybe $47, and so on.  There will be sudden drops now and then, but the general trend is upward.

Obviously, estimates of the intrinsic value of a given security will be different for different investors.  A useful way to estimate that value for a security you own is to ask yourself the question: what is the most you would be willing to pay for the security if you couldn’t ever sell it?  Take the S&P 500 with its $45 dividend that grows at some pace over the long-term–say, 2% real, plus or minus profit-related uncertainty.  What is the most that you would be willing to pay to own a share of the S&P 500, assuming you would be stuck owning it forever?  Put differently, at what ratio would you be willing to permanently convert your present money, which you can use right now to purchase anything you want, including other assets, into a slowly accumulating dividend stream that you cannot use to make purchases, at least not until the individual dividends are received?

When I poll people on that question, I get very bearish answers.  By and large, I find that people would be unwilling to own the current S&P 500 for any yield below 5%, which corresponds to a S&P 500 price of at most 1000.  The actual S&P trades at roughly 2365, which should tell you how much liquidity–i.e., the ability to take out the money that you put into an investment–matters to investors.  In the case of the S&P 500, it represents more than half of the asset’s realized market value.

Now, here’s where the parallel to banking comes into play.  As with a bank, a market’s liquidity is backed by a network of confidence among its participants.  Participants trust that there will be other participants willing to buy at prices near or above the current price, and therefore they themselves are willing to buy, confident that they will not lose access to their money for any sustained period of time.   Their buying, in turn, supports the market’s pricing and creates an observable outcome–price stability–that reinforces trust in it. Because the investors don’t all rush for the exits at the same time, they don’t have a need to rush for the exits.  They can rationally collect the excess returns that the market is offering, even though those returns would be insufficient to cover the cost of lost liquidity.

When the network of confidence breaks down, you end up with a situation where people are holding securities, nervous about a possible loss of access to their money, while prevailing prices are still way above intrinsic value, i.e., way above the prices that they would demand in order to compensate for a loss of liquidity. So they sell whatever they can, driving prices lower and lower, until confidence in a new price level re-emerges. Prices rarely go all the way down to intrinsic value, but when they do, investors end up with generational buying opportunities.

Recall that in our earlier example, you have two options.  You can hold your money in a safe, or you can hold it in a bank.  The safe gives you absolute security–no possibility of ever losing access to the money.  The bank gives you a 2.5% extra return, plus convenience, all in exchange for risk to your access.  Granted, you can get your money out of the bank whenever you want–but only if the network of confidence that backs its liquidity remains intact.  Because you believe that the network of confidence will remain intact, you choose the convenience and the added return.  Our modernized banking system simplifies the choice dramatically by externally bolstering the network through the use of mutual insurance and the designation of a lender of last resort.  And so there’s not even a question as to whether you should take the convenience and additional 2.5% return that the bank is offering.  You should take any extra return at all, all the way down to zero, because there’s essentially no risk that the network that backs your access to the money will ever break down.

Investors face a similar choice.  They can hold their money in cash, and earn a low return–in the current case, 0%–or they can purchase an asset.  The cash gives them absolute, unrestricted access to their money at all times, whereas the asset gives them imperfect access, access that’s contingent, at least in part, on the sustained preferences and expectations of other investors.  In compensation for that risk, they get an extra return, often a large extra return.

The question comes up: in a low rate world, with assets at historically high valuations, offering historically low returns, what should investors do?  Should they opt to own assets, or should they hold cash?  The point I want to make in all of this is that to answer the question, we need to gauge the likely strength and sustainability of the market’s network of confidence amid those stipulated conditions.  We need to ask ourselves whether investors are likely to remain willing to buy at the high valuations and low implied returns that they’ve been buying at.  If the conclusion is that they will remain willing, then it makes all the sense in the world to buy assets and continue to own them.  And if the conclusion is that they won’t remain willing, that something will change, then it makes all the sense in the world to choose hold cash instead.

If we’re living in a low-rate world, and our only option other than holding cash is to buy the S&P at 30 times earnings, or a 30 year treasury at 2%, or whatever other shitty deal is on offer, and you ask me what we should do, I can only answer the question by asking whether there will continue to be a ready supply of buyers at those valuations into the future.  And the point is, regardless of what “historical averages” have to say about the matter, there may continue to be!  As always, path is crucial.  If valuations have arrived at their current levels through short-term excitement and mania, then we should be more suspicious of their forward-looking sustainability.  The network of confidence sustaining those valuations is likely to be fickle and to eventually break down.  But if prices have gradually moved to where they are over a long period of time, in response to legitimate secular market forces and conditions, if participants have had sufficient time to grow accustomed to them, to psychologically anchor to them, such that they see them as normal and appropriate, then the basis for questioning their sustainability isn’t going to be as strong.

It’s important to remember that as long as cash is yielding zero or something very low, there’s no arbitrage to 苹果的梯子 asset prices lower, no dynamic to force them to conform to some historically observed level or average.  They can go as high as they want to, and stay as high as they want to, provided investors are able to develop and retain the confidence to buy at those levels.  Note that the same point doesn’t hold as readily in the other direction, when considering how low prices can go.  That’s because financial assets have intrinsic value.  Below that value, they’re worth owning purely for their cash flow streams, regardless of the prices at which they can be sold.  The market can take those prices all the way to down to zero, they’ll still be worth owning as incoming cash flow streams.

People won’t like to hear this, but in the same way that policymakers have introduced structures and practices into the banking system designed to bolster the networks of confidence that sustain banking liquidity, policymakers are capable of introducing structures and practices into financial markets that bolster the networks of confidence that sustain market liquidity.  For example, in order to prevent sharp drops that would otherwise be economically harmful, policymakers can use public money to buy equities themselves, providing a direct backstop.  Or if that’s not an option legally, they can talk up financial markets, accompanying the talk with whatever policy tools market participants find compelling.  If it’s the case, as some argue, that policymaker approaches around the world are evolving in that direction, then that provides yet another basis for valuations to get pushed higher, just as it provided a basis in our earlier example for a depositor to keep money in a bank despite being paid a paltry rate.

It’s often said that bank solvency is an unhelpful concept, given that a bank’s ability to survive is often determined more by its liquidity condition than by anything happening on its balance sheet.  Every bank can survive a solvency crisis if given enough liquidity, and every bank can be put into a solvency crisis if starved of enough liquidity.  Some would argue, for example, that Lehman failed not because it was 苹果翻墙梯子, if that even means anything, but because the Fed, right or wrong, refused to lend to it when no one else would.  It couldn’t survive the crunch it faced, so it folded.  In hindsight, we conclude that it was insolvent.  But was it?  It’s something of a stretch, but we can find an analogy here to stock market valuation.  Every stock market, in hindsight, is seen as having been “expensive” or in a “bubble” when the network of confidence that holds it together breaks down, i.e., when people panic and sell out of it, driving it sharply lower.  And every stock market, in hindsight, is seen as “fairly valued” when it suffers no panic and slowly appreciates as it’s supposed to do.

With respect to equity markets in particular, I’ll end with this. If we want to get in front of things that are going to break a market’s network of confidence and undermine people’s beliefs that they’ll be able to sell near or above where they’ve been buying, we shouldn’t be focusing on valuation.  We should be focusing instead on factors and forces that actually do cause panics, that actually do break the networks of confidence that hold markets together.  We should be focusing on conditions and developments in the real economy, in the corporate sector, in the banking system, in the credit markets, and so on, looking for imbalances and vulnerabilities that, when they unwind and unravel, will sour the moods of investors, bring their fears and anxieties to the surface, and cause them to question the sustainability of prevailing prices, regardless of the valuations at which the process happens to begin.

Posted in 苹果的梯子 | Comments OffiPhone如何挂梯子

有个V字图标免费加速器

In this piece, I’m going to introduce a simplified model of a fund market, and then use the model to illustrate certain important concepts related to the impact of the market’s ongoing transition from active to passive management.  Some of the concepts have already been discussed in prior pieces, others are going to be new to this piece.

bb梯子游戏苹果版下载-android版:2021-6-13 · bb梯子游戏苹果版下载Android6.1.x众上,bb梯子游戏正版APP下载(Vv4.6.4是当下苹果IOS、安卓版流行速度快的APP(18.28M),音乐地图数据精确及时,android版下载安装量达492584人次,bb梯子游戏最新版深受大家喜欢的APP软件;

苹果翻墙梯子

The market is characterized by the following facts:

  • Share ownership by individuals is not allowed.  The only way to own shares is to invest in a fund, and there are no funds to invest in other the 1,000 funds already specified. All shares in existence are held somewhere inside those funds.
  • The passive fund is required to target a 100% allocation to equities over the long-term, holding shares of each company in relative proportion to the total number of shares in existence.
  • The active funds are required to target a 95% allocation to equities over the long-term. They are free to implement that allocation in whatever way they want–i.e., by holding shares of whatever companies they prefer.  The 95% number is chosen because it leaves the active funds with enough cash to trade, but not so much cash as to appreciably detract from their returns.  Note that from here forward, when we refer to the “returns” of the active funds, we will be referring to the returns of the portion of the funds that are actually invested in the market, not the overall returns of the funds, which will include the returns of a certain amount of cash held for the purposes of liquidity.
  • The passive fund and the group of 999 active funds each represent roughly half of the overall market, a fact represented in the identical sizing of the grey boxes in the schematic above.
  • Each active fund charges an annual management fee of 1%.  The passive fund is publicly-administered and charges no fees.

We can separate the market’s valuation into two dimensions: (1) absolute valuation and (2) relative valuation.

(1) Absolute Valuation: Valuation of the aggregate market relative to cash.

(2) Relative Valuation: Valuation of companies in the market relative to each other.

If we know these two dimensions, then, assuming we know the fundamentals of the underlying companies (earnings, dividends, etc.), we can infer the exact prices of all shares in the market.

Importantly, the two dimensions of the market’s valuation are controlled by two distinct entities:

  • The fund investors control the market’s absolute valuation through their net cash injections and withdrawals (see green and red arrows, respectively).  They cannot control the market’s relative valuation because they cannot trade in individual shares.
  • The active funds control the market’s relative valuation through their buying and selling of individual shares.  They cannot control the market’s absolute valuation because they are not allowed to try to increase or decrease their long-term allocations to equities.

The passive funds control nothing, because they have no freedom in any aspect of their market behaviors.  They must deploy 100% of any funds they receive into equities, and they must buy and sell shares so as to establish positions that are in exact relative proportion to the supply outstanding.

iphone苹果如何打开Youtube可众用的苹果翻墙油管知乎免费 ...:解决苹果手机如何上Youtube,ipad如何打开Youtube,ios怎么注册Youtube油管,2021电脑PC端可众用的稳定vpn账号密码翻墙软件美国香港ios苹果iphone手机梯子安卓Android节点知乎免费推荐国外付费ssr科学上网游戏视频vpn路由器账号密码

Suppose that an investor sends new cash into a fund–either the passive fund or one of the 999 active funds–and that everything else in the system remains unchanged.  The receiving fund will have an allocation target that it will have to follow.  It will therefore have to use the cash to buy shares.  But the receiving fund cannot buy shares unless some other fund sells shares.  That other fund–the selling fund–will also have an allocation target that it will have to follow.  It will therefore have to use the cash from the sale to buy shares from yet another fund, which will have to use the cash from the sale to buy shares from yet another fund, which will have to use the cash from the sale to buy shares from yet another fund, and so on.  Instead of sitting quietly in the hands of the fund that it was injected into, the cash will get tossed around from fund to fund across the market like a hot potato.

How long will the tossing around of the hot potato (cash) last?  At a minimum, it will last until prices rise by an amount sufficient to lift the aggregate equity capitalization of the market to a level that allows all funds to be at their target equity allocations amid the higher absolute amount of cash in the system.  Only then will an equilibrium be possible.

To illustrate, suppose that each fund in the system is required to target an allocation of 95% equity, and 5% cash.  Consistent with that allocation, suppose that there is $95MM of iPhone如何挂梯子 market equity in the system, and $5MM of aggregate cash. (95MM/$100MM = 95% equity, and $5MM/$100MM = 5% cash, so there’s a sufficient supply of each asset for every fund to satisfy its allocation mandate.)  Suppose that investors then inject $5MM of new cash into the system, raising the total amount of cash to $10MM.  That injection will throw the funds’ allocations out of balance.  As a group, they will find themselves under-invested in equity relative to their targets, and will therefore have to buy shares.  They will have to persist in that effort until prices rise by an amount sufficient to increase the system’s aggregate equity market capitalization to $190MM, which is the only number that will allow every fund to have a 95% allocation to equity amid the higher amount of cash ($10MM) in the system. ($190MM/$200MM = 95% equity, and $10MM/$200MM = 5% cash, leaving a sufficient supply of each asset for every fund to satisfy its allocation mandate.)

When cash is removed from the system, the same process takes place in reverse–prices get pulled down by the selling until the aggregate equity market capitalization falls to a level that allows the funds to be at their allocation targets amid the lower absolute amount of cash in the system.

Now, the process by which investor flows drive valuations in our hypothetical market is subject to the same natural feedbacks seen in any real market.  As prices go up, the market’s valuation and implied future return becomes less attractive, therefore fewer investors send cash in, more investors take cash out, and prices see downward pressure:

Prices Up –> Demand Down –> Prices Down (Negative Feedback)

Conversely, as prices go down, the market’s valuation and implied future return becomes more attractive, therefore more investors send cash in, fewer investors take cash out, and prices see upward pressure:

Prices Down –> Demand Up –> Prices Up (Negative Feedback)

As in any real market, there are situations in which this natural negative feedback can give way to a different kind of positive feedback, where rising prices reflexively lead to greater optimism and confidence, fueling increased buying, decreased selling, and therefore further price increases:

Prices Up –> Demand Up –> Prices Up (More) (Positive Feedback)

…and, conversely, where falling prices reflexively lead to greater pessimism and fear, fueling decreased buying, increased selling, and therefore further price declines:

Prices Down –> Demand Down –> Prices Down (More) (Positive Feedback)

I highlight the details here simply to point out that the feedback processes governing prices in our hypothetical market are no different from the feedback processes that govern prices in real markets.  The only difference is in the artificial “fund” structure that we’ve imposed, a structure that helps us separate out and explore the different components of price formation.

Relative Valuation: Driven by Active Fund Preferences

一键解除iOS版Telegram对群组和频道的限制 - 吾晓科技:2021-3-20 · 不过受限于苹果的政策,iOS 平台上的 Telegram 官方 APP 限制访问特定的群组或频道,例如包含色情或盗版信息的那部分就被阻止了。 如何突破限制,成为众多用户头疼的事情。往常的做法是使用第三方客户端,不过这个选择有很大的风险,因为用户 ...

梯子助手怎么用-百度经验:2021-12-10 · 梯子助手怎么用,助手的应用有利于科学论文的研究,能及时跟进国际上的先进知识,通过分析得出实验结果并且应用,那么助手工具到底应该怎么用呢?本文介绍有关经验众供参考。

To answer the question, imagine a society where coins are the primary form of money, and where people generally hold coins in their pockets.  Suppose further that in this society, there are a select group of careless people who fail to buy new pants on a recurring basis, and who therefore end up with holes in their pockets.  As these people walk around the society, they unknowingly drop coins on the floor, leaving coins laying around for other passers-by to pick up and profit from.  A savvy individual recognizes the profit opportunity asssociated with the “mistakes” these coin-droppers are making, and develops a way to skillfully “arbitrage” them.  Specifically, he builds a super-whamodyne metal detector, which he uses to go on sophisticated coin hunts throughout the society.  With this super-whamodyne metal detector, he is able to pick up falling and hidden coins much faster than anyone else, and therefore generates an outsized profit for himself.

Clearly, his coin-hunting activities will generate a micro-level benefit for him.  But, aside from possible street cleanliness (fewer coins laying around?), are there any 苹果翻墙梯子 macro-level benefits that will be generated for the overall society?  No.  Any “profit” that he earns in finding a given coin will be the mirror image of the loss incurred by whoever dropped it, or whoever failed to pick it up in front of him.  His effort will benefit him, but the benefit will always occur alongside corresponding losses or missed gains for others.  The system as a whole will see no net gain.  From a macro-level perspective, the resources expended in the effort to build the super-whamodyne metal detector, and lug it all around the society in search of treasure, will have been completely wasted.

We can think of market arbitrage in the same way.  Some market participants make mistakes.  Other market participants expend vast resources trying to arbitrage those mistakes, with an emphasis on getting their first, in order to capture the profit.  No value is generated in the process; rather, value is simply transferred from the mistake-makers to the arbitrageurs, just as it was transferred from the coin-droppers to the coin-hunter. From a macro-level perspective, the resources expended in the effort end up being wasted.

Now, to be fair, this argument neglects the fact that prices in a market impact capital formation, which in turn impacts an economy’s resource allocation.  When a money-losing, value-destroying business is given an undeservedly high price, it is able to raise capital more easily, and is therefore more able to direct additional economic resources into its money-losing, value-destroying operation, where the resources are likely to be wasted. Conversely, when a profitable, value-generating business is given an undeservedly low price, it is less able to raise capital, and is therefore less able to direct economic resources into its profitable, value-generating operation, where they would otherwise have been put to beneficial economic use.

Personally, I tend to be skeptical of the alleged relationship between equity prices and capital formation.  Corporations rarely fund their investment programs through equity issuance, and so there’s no reason for there to be any meaningful relationship.  This is especially true for the mature companies that make up the majority of the equity market’s capitalization–companies that comprise the vast majority of the portfolio holdings on which active management fees get charged.

To illustrate the point with an example, suppose that the market were to irrationally double the price of Pepsi $PEP, and irrationally halve the price of Coke $KO.  Would the change have any meaningful effect on the real economy?  In a worst case scenario, maybe $PEP would divert excess income away from share buybacks towards dividends, or arbitrage its capital structure by selling equity to buy back debt.  Maybe $KO would do the opposite–divert excess income from away dividends towards share buybacks, or arbitrage its capital structure by selling debt to buy back equity.  Either way, who cares?  What difference would it make to the real economy?  For the shift to impact the real economy, it would have to be the case that money used for share repurchases and dividends and other types of financial engineering is deployed at the direct expense of money used for business investment, which evidence shows is not the case, at least not for large companies such as these.  The companies make the investments in their businesses that they need to make in order to compete and profitably serve their expected future demand opportunities. Whatever funds are left over, they return to their shareholders, or devote to financial arbitrage.

Many investors believe that the current equity market is excessively expensive, having been inflated to an extreme valuation by the Federal Reserve’s easy monetary policy.  Let’s assume that the most vocal of these investors are right, and that stocks in the market are at least ios能用的梯子2022 as expensive as they should be.  The Fed, then, has ios能用的梯子2022 the market’s valuation–or alternatively, has halved the equity funding costs of corporations.  Ask yourself: is this alleged “distortion” leading to excessive corporate investment?  No, not at all.  If the current economy were experiencing excessive corporate investment, then we would be experiencing an inflationary economic boom right now.  But we’re experiencing nothing of the sort–if anything, we’re experiencing the opposite, a period of slumpy moderation, despite being more than 7 years into an expansion.  That’s because, contrary to the Fed’s better intentions, the transmission mechanism from share prices to real investment is weak.

Absolute and Relative Valuation: Samuelson’s Dictum

The price dynamics seen in our hypothetical market are obviously different from the price dynamics seen in real markets.  In real markets, individual investors are allowed to invest directly in individual shares, which allows them to directly influence relative valuations inside the equity space.  Similarly, in real markets, many of the active funds that invest in equities–for example, hedge funds–are able to significantly vary their net exposures to equities as an asset class. This ability allows them to directly influence the equity market’s absolute valuation.

With that said, there’s probably some truth to the model’s implication.  Individual investors (as well as the first-level custodians that manage their money, e.g., RIAs) probably exert greater control over the market’s absolute valuation.  That’s because they directly control flows into and out of investment vehicles that have no choice but to be fully invested in equities–e.g., active and passive equity mutual funds and ETFs.   Conversely, they probably exert less control over the relative valuation of shares inside the equity market, because they’re less likely to be the ones directly speculating inside that space, opting to rely on the available investment vehicles instead.

In contrast, the professional managers that operate downstream of individual investor flows, and that manage the various investment vehicles that provide those investors with equity exposure, probably exert less control over the market’s absolute valuation.  That’s because when flows come into or go out of their vehicles, they have to buy and sell, which means they have to put the associated buying and selling pressures somewhere into the market.  They cannot opt to “hold” the pressure as a buffer–they have to pass it  on. Conversely, they probably exert greater control over the relative valuation of shares inside the market, given that source investors often step aside and leave the task of making relative trades in the market to them, based on their expertise.

This fact may be the reason for Samuelson’s famous observation that markets are more efficient at the micro-level than at the macro-level.  If micro-level decisions–e.g., decisions about which specific companies in the equity market to own–are more likely to be made by professionals that possess experience and skill in security selection, then we should expect markets to be more efficient at the micro-level.  Conversely, if macro-level decisions–e.g., decisions about what basic asset classes to invest in, whether to be invested in anything at all, i.e., whether to just hold cash, and how much cash to hold–are more likely to be made at the source level, by the unsophisticated individuals that allocate their wealth to various parts of the system, individuals that are in no way inclined to optimize the timing of the flows they introduce, then we should expect markets to be less efficient at the macro-level.

We should note, of course, that the concept of efficiency is far more difficult to make sense of at the macro-level, where the different assets–cash, fixed income, and equities–are orthogonal to each other, i.e., of a totally different kind.  The advantages and disadvantages associated with holding them cannot be easily expressed in each other’s terms.

To illustrate, a share of Google $GOOG and a share of Amazon $AMZN are the same general kind of asset–an equity security, an intrinsically-illiquid stream of potential future dividends paid out of future free cash flows.  Because they are the same general kind of asset, it is easier to express the value of one in terms of the value of the other.  If, at every point into the future, a $GOOG share will generate double the free cash flow of the $AMZN share, then it has double the value, and should be double the price; similarly, if it will generate half the free cash flow, then it obviously has half the value, and should be half the price.

A share of Google $GOOG and a dollar bill, in contrast, are not the same kind of asset–one is an equity security, an intrinsically-illiquid stream of future monetary payments, the other is fully-liquid present money, in hand right now for you to use in whatever way you please.  Because they are not the same kind of asset, there is no easy way to put the two asset types together onto the same plane, no necessary, non-arbitrary ratio that one can cite to express the value that one posseses in terms of the other–e.g., 710 dollars for every $GOOG share.  But that is precisely what it means to “value” them.

The Active Management Fee: Can it Be Earned?

Now, let’s be fair.  In working to establish “correct prices”, active funds in a secondary market do provide macro-level benefits for the economy.  It’s just that the benefits are small, frequently exaggerated in their actual economic impacts.  As compensation for the work they perform in those efforts, the funds charge a fee–in our hypothetical example, the fee was 1% of assets.  To earn that 1% fee, the funds need to outperform the market by 1% iPhone如何挂梯子.  As a group, is it possible for them to do that?

The temptation is to say no, it is not possible.  The passive fund is holding the market portfolio.  Since the passive fund plus the collection of active funds equals the overall market, it follows that the active funds, collectively, are also holding the market portfolio. Given that the two segments of the market–passive and active–are holding the same portfolios, it’s logically impossible for one segment to outperform the other.  In previous pieces, we called this observation, attributable to William Sharpe, “The Law of Conservation of Alpha.”  Aggregate alpha in a market must always sum to zero.

The Law of Conservation of Alpha seems to leave us no choice but to conclude that the active funds in our hypothetical system will simply underperform the passive fund by the amount of their fees–in the current case, 1%–and that the underperformance will continue forever and ever, never being made up for.  But if that’s the case, then why would any rational investor choose to invest in active funds?

Imagine that there are two asset classes, A and B, and that you have the option of investing in one or the other.  Suppose that you know, with absolute certainty, that asset class B is going to underperform asset class A by 1%.  Knowing that fact, why would you choose to invest in asset class B over asset class A?  Why would you choose to invest in the asset class with the ios翻外墙用什么 expected return?

It makes sense for investors to accept lower returns in exchange for lower amounts of risk. But, in this case, the group of active funds are not offering lower risk in comparison with the passive fund.  They are offering the exact same risk, because they are holding the exact same portfolio.  In fact, there’s a relevant sense in which the active funds, considered individually, are offering additional risk in comparison with the passive fund–specifically, the additional risk of underperforming or outperforming the benchmark.  To be fair, that risk may not be a clear net negative in the same way that volatility is a net negative, but it certainly isn’t a net positive, and therefore it makes no sense for investors to throw away 1% in annual return, every year, year after year, in exchange for the highly dubious “privilege” of taking it on.

What we have in our hypothetical market is an obvious arbitrage–go with the passive fund, and earn an extra 1% per year in expected return, with no strings attached.  As investors become increasingly aware of that arbitrage, we should expect them to shift their investments out of the active funds and into the passive fund, a transition that is taking place in real markets as we speak.  Our intuitions tell us that there should be adverse consequences associated with the transition.  As more and more investors opt to free-ride on a passive approach, pocketing the 1% instead of paying it, we should expect there to be negative impacts on the market’s functioning.

In a previous piece, I argued that there were impacts on the market’s functioning–but that, surprisingly, they were 苹果翻墙梯子 impacts.  Counter-intuitively, the transition out of active funds and into passive funds makes the market more efficient in its relative pricing of shares, because it preferentially removes lower-skilled players from the active segment of the market, leaving a higher average level of skill in the remaining pool of market participants to set prices.  I extended the argument to include the impact on retail investors, who, in being persuaded to take on equity market exposures through passive vehicles, rather than by picking individual stocks or active fund managers themselves, were rendered less likely to inject their own lack of skill into the market’s relative pricing mechanism.  Granted, they will be just as likely to distort the market’s absolute valuation through their knee-jerk inflows and outflows into the market as a whole, but at least they will not be exerting additional influences on the market’s relative valuation, where their lack of skill would end up producing additional distortions.

Now, if market participants were to shift to a passive approach in the practice of asset allocation more broadly–that is, if they were to resolve to hold cash, fixed income, and equity from around the globe in relative proportion to the total supplies outstanding–then we would expect to see a similarly positive impact on the market’s absolute pricing mechanism, particularly as unskilled participants choose to take passive approaches with respect to those asset classes in lieu of attempts to “time” them.  But, to be clear, a broader shift to that broader kind of passivity is not currently ongoing.  The only areas where “passive” approaches are increasing in popularity are areas inside specific asset classes–specifically, inside the equity and fixed income markets of the developed world.

Active to Passive: The Emergence of Distortion

Passive investing may improve the market’s efficiency at various incremental phases of the transition, but there are limits to the improvement.  To appreciate those limits, let’s assume that the migration from active to passive in our hypothetical market continues over the long-term, and that the number of active funds in the system ends up shrinking down to a tiny fraction of its initial size.  Whereas the active segment of the market initially consisted of 999 active funds collectively controlling roughly 50% of equity assets, let’s assume that the active segment shrinks down to only 10 funds collectively controlling 0.5% of equity assets.  The other 99.5% of the market migrates into the passive fund.

ios能用的梯子2022

In evaluating the impact of this shift, it’s important to remember that active investors are the entities that set prices in a market.  Passive investors cannot set prices, first because they do not have any fundamental notion of the correct prices to set, and second because their transactions are forced to occur immediately in order to preserve the passivity of their allocations–they cannot simply lay out desired bids and asks and wait indefinitely for the right prices to come, because the right prices may never come.  To lay out a desired bid and ask, and then wait, is to speculate on the future price, and passive funds don’t do that.  They take whatever price is there.

In the above configuration, then, the tiny segment of the market that remains active–which holds roughly 0.5% of the total equity supply–will have to set prices for all 5,000 securities in the market.  It follows that a much smaller pool of resources will be devoted to doing the “work”–i.e., the fundamental research, the due-diligence, etc.–necessary to set prices correctly.  For that reason, we should expect the configuration to substantially reduce the market’s efficiency, contrary to what I asserted earlier.

In our hypothetical market, a 1% active management fee was initially being levied on 50% of the market’s capitalization, with the proceeds used to fund the cost of due-diligence. After the migration, that 1% fee will be levied on only 0.5% of the market’s capitalization, yielding roughly 1/100 of the proceeds.  The shrunken proceeds will have to pay for the cost of due-diligence on a security universe that hasn’t shrunken at all.  Because the active segment will have a much smaller amount of money to spend on the due-diligence process, a new investor that enters and spends a given amount of money on it in competition with the active segment will be more likely to gain an edge over it.  At the margin, active investors that enter at the margin will be more capable of beating the market, which is precisely what it means for the market to be less efficient.

This thinking is headed in the right direction, but there’s a subtle problem with it.  The best way to see that problem is to trace out the literal process by which the active segment will end up shrinking.  Suppose we return to where we initially started, with 999 active funds and 1 passive funds.  In their efforts to arbitrage the 1% differential in expected returns, investors transfer large sums of money out of the 100 active funds with the worst performance track records, and into the market-performing passive fund, forcing the 100 active funds to shut down.

The 100 active funds that end up shutting down will have to sell their shares to raise cash to redeem their investors.  But who will they sell their shares to?  They might be able to sell some of their shares to the passive fund, because it will be receiving cash inflows, and will need to buy shares.  But they won’t be able to sell all of their shares to the passive fund, because the passive fund will have to buy shares of every company in the market–all 5,000, in proportion to the supply oustanding–many of which the active funds won’t be holding.  The passive funds will therefore have no choice but to buy at least some of their shares from the other 899 active funds that remain.

Working out the implications of the flows, then, the 100 underperforming active funds, in liquidating themselves, will have to sell at least some of their shares to the 899 remaining active funds.  Those remaining active funds will be in a position to buy the shares, because they will have received cash from selling some of their own shares to the passive fund when it went in to buy.  But before the remaining active funds can buy the new shares, they will have to conduct research–due-diligence–to determine the appropriate prices. That due-diligence will cost money.  Where will the money come from?

Unfortunately, there is nowhere for it to come from, because the assets that the remaining active funds will have under management, and therefore the fee revenues that they will be able to earn, will not have increased.  Crucially, in the migration, assets will not be moving from the 100 underperforming active funds to the remaining active funds who will perform the needed fundamental research on the shares being sold–rather, assets will be moving from the 100 underperforming funds to the cheapskate passive fund, which doesn’t spend any money at all on the research process, opting to simply give the money back to its investors instead.  Consequently, the money needed to fund the additional research will not be available.  Unless the money is taken out of some other necessary research activity, or out of the active fund manager’s wages or profits, the research and due-diligence necessary to buy the shares will not get done.

The following two schematics distinguish two types of migrations: a sustainable migration from active fund to active fund, and an unsustainable migration from active fund to passive fund.

activetoactive

Fund2topassive

In our scenario, the remaining active funds will not have done the research necessary to buy the shares that the underperforming funds will need to sell, and will not get paid any additional money to do that research.  Consequently, they aren’t going to be interested in buying the shares.  But the 100 underperforming active funds have to sell the shares–they have to get cash to redeem their investors.  So what will happen?  The answer: the bid-ask spread will effectively widen.  Prices will be found at which the remaining active funds will be willing to transact–those prices will simply be much lower, to ensure adequate protection for the funds, given that they haven’t done the work necessary to be comfortable with the purchases, or alternatively, given that they need to pay for that work, and that the money has to come from somewhere.

The point articulated here is admittedly cumbersome, and it might seem out of place to think about the process in terms of the need to pay for “research.”  But the point is entirely accurate.  The best way to grasp it is to start from the endgame scenario that we posited, a scenario where active funds shrink down to some absurdly small size–say, 0.5% of the market, with the other 99.5% of the market invested passively.  How do you get to a situation where a measly 0.5% of the market, a tiny group of managers that are only able to draw in a tiny revenue stream out of which to pay for fundamental research, is setting prices–placing bids and asks–on a massive equity universe consisting of 5,000 complicated securities?  The ios能用的梯子2022 way you get there is by having bid-ask spreads completely blow out.  If their counterparties are desperate, then yes, the tiny group of active funds will trade in securities that they aren’t familiar with or interested in, and that they haven’t done adequate due-diligence on.  But they will only do so at prices that are sufficient to provide them with extreme margins of safety: ultra-low bids if they have to be the buyers, and ultra-high asks if they have to be the sellers.

In the previous piece on Indexville, we posed the question: what will happen if the active segment of the market becomes too small, or if it goes away completely?  Most people think the answer is that the market will become “inefficient”, priced incorrectly relative to fundamentals, making it easier for new active investors to enter the fray and outperform. But we saw that that’s not exactly the right answer.  The right answer is that the market will become illiquid.  The bid-ask spread will blow out or disappear entirely, making it increasingly costly, or even impossible, for investors–whether passive or active–to transact in the ways that they want to.

The example above takes us to that same conclusion by a different path.  If an active segment with a tiny asset base and tiny fee revenues is left to set prices on a large universe of complicated securities, the bid-ask spreads necessary to get that segment to transact will explode, particularly in those securities that it has not done sufficient research on and that it is not familiar with or comfortable transacting in–which will be most securities, given that a tiny segment of a large market cannot single-handedly do the work of studying and forming a sound fundamental opinion on ios能用的梯子2022 inside it.

Liquidity Provision: A Way to Earn the Fees

We return to the question at the title of the previous section: Can the fees that active managers collectively charge be earned?  The answer is yes.  The fees can be earned out of revenues generated through the provision of liquidity–selling at the ask to those that need to buy, and buying at the bid from those that need to sell.  The excess return over the market equals half the spread between the two, times the volume, divided by the capital employed.  As the active segment of the market shrinks in size, that excess return will increase.  At the same time, the fees extracted by the segment will decrease, bringing the segment closer to a condition in which its fees match its excess returns, which is what it means for the active segment to ios可众用的梯子 its fees.

The active segment of the market has two external counterparties that it can provide liquidity to: first, the passive segment, which experiences inflows and outflows that it must deploy and redeem, and second, the corporate sector, which sometimes needs to raise equity funding, and which, more frequently in the present era, wants to buy back its own shares.  The total flows of those external counterparties–the total amount of buying and selling that they engage in–will determine the amount of excess return that the active segment can generate in providing liquidity to them, and therefore the maximum fees that it can collectively “earn.”  Any fees that get extracted above that amount will be uncompensated for, taken from investors in exchange for nothing.

If the market were suffering from an inadequate amount of active management, the consequences would become evident in the performance of passive funds.  Passive funds would begin to exhibit increased tracking errors relative to their benchmarks.  Every time they received a cash inflow and attempted to buy shares, they would be forced to buy at the elevated ask prices set by the small number of active funds willing and able to transact with them, ask prices that they would push up through their attempted buying. Conversely, every time they received redemption requests and attempted to sell shares, they would be forced to sell at the depressed bid prices set by the small number of active funds willing to transact with them, bid prices that they would pull down through their attempted selling.  On each round-trip, each buy followed by a sell, they would lodge a tracking loss relative to their indices, the mirror image of which would be the excess profit earned by the active segment in providing them with liquidity.

Now, you might think that liquidity in the market is already provided by specialized market-makers–e.g., computers trading on HFT algorithms–and that active, fundamentally-informed investors are not needed.  But market-makers of that type only provide one small phase of the market’s liquidity–the phase that entails bridging together, over the very short-term, the temporarily divergent flows of participants that are seeking to hold shares for longer periods of time.  Active investors, those that are willing to adjust their demand for shares based on fundamental value, are crucial to the rest of the process, because they are the only entities that are capable of buffering and balancing out longer-term flow imbalances that otherwise emerge in the market–situations, for example, where there is an excess of interested sellers, but no interested buyers, either present or en route, even after the ask price is substantially lowered.  Without the participation of value-responsive active investors in those situations, market-makers would have no buyers to bridge the selling flows against, and would therefore have to widen their spreads, i.e., lower their bids–or even remove them from the market altogether.

Right now, the average tracking error in the average passive fund is imperceptible.  This fact is proof that the current market, in its ongoing migration into passive funds, isn’t even close to suffering from an insufficiency of active management.  With at most 40% of the equity market having gone passive, the point in the transition where tangible market illiquidity will ensue is still very far away.

That’s why, in the previous piece, I argued that the active segment of the market is not even close to being able to earn its fees in the aggregate.  Active managers aren’t doing anything wrong per se, it’s just that the shrinkage they’ve suffered hasn’t yet been extreme enough to undermine the function they provide, or make the provision of that function profitable enough to reimburse the fees charged in providing it.  Granted, they may be able to earn their fees by exploiting “dumb-money” categories that we haven’t modeled in our hypothetical market–e.g., retail investors that choose to conduct uninformed speculation in individual shares, and that leave coins on the floor for skilled managers to pick up behind them–but they aren’t even close to being able to collectively earn their fees via the liquidity they provide to the other segments of the market, which, evidently, are doing just fine.

The Actual Forces Sustaining Active Management

Active managers, in correctly setting prices in the market, provide a necessary benefit to the economy.  In a mature, developed economy like ours, where the need for corporate investment is low, and where the corporate sector is able to finance that need out of its own internal cash flows, the benefit tends to be small.  But it’s still a benefit, a contribution that a society should have to pay for.

Right now, the people that are paying for the benefit are the people that, for whatever reason, choose to invest in the active segment of the market, the segment that does the work necessary to set prices correctly, and that charges a fee for that work.  But why do investors do that?  Why do they invest in the active segment of the market, when they know that doing so will leave them with a lower return on average, in exchange for nothing?

The question would be more apt if active investors were investing in a fund that owned shares of all actively-managed funds–an aggregate fund-of-all-active-funds, if one can envision such a monstrosity.  Investors in such a fund would be giving away the cost of fees in exchange for literally nothinga return that would otherwise be absolutely identical to the passive alternative in every conceivable respect, except for the useless drag of the fees.

But that is not what people that invest in the active segment of the market are actually doing.  Active management is not a group sport; the investors that invest in it are not investing in the “group.”  Rather, they are investing in the individual active managers that they themselves have determined to be uniquely skilled.  It’s true that they pay a fee to do that, but in exchange for that fee, they get the possibility of outperformance–a possibility that they evidently consider to be likely.

Every investor that rationally chooses to invest in the active segment of the market makes the choice on that basis–an expectation of outperformance driven by the apparent skill of the individual active manager that the investor has picked out.  Whereas this choice can make sense in individual cases, it cannot make sense in the average case, because the average of the group will always be just that–average in performance, i.e., not worth extra fees.  In choosing to invest in the active segment, then, active investors are choosing, as a group, to be the gracious individuals that pay for the cost of having “correct market prices”, in exchange for nothing.  Passive investors are then able to free-ride on that gracious gift.

How, then, is the active segment of the market able to remain so large, particularly in an environment where the fees charged are so high, so much more than the 苹果翻墙梯子 cost of doing the fundamental research necessary to have a well-functioning market?  Why don’t more active investors instead choose the passive option, which would allow them to avoid paying the costs of having a well-functioning market, and which would net them a higher average return in the final analysis?

The answer, in my view, is two-fold:

(1) 【IOS】手把手教你如何登陆switch online【无需梯...:2021-4-22 · 应该是就两种办法吧:1.搭梯子 把图从switch直接上传到twitter或fb后用手机下载看;2.用读卡器把 应该是就两种办法吧:1.搭梯子 把图从switch直接上传到twitter或fb后用手机下载看;2.用读卡器把相册的图导出来... 元気少女俊一基:  For every active manager, there will always be some group of investors somewhere that will be persuaded by her argument that she has skill, and that will be eager to invest with her on the promise of a higher return, even though it is strictly impossible for the ios翻外墙用什么 group of managers engaged in that persuasive effort to actually fulfill the promise.  Moreover, absent a strong impetus, many investors will tend to stay where they are, invested in whatever they’ve been invested in–including in active funds that have failed to deliver on that promise.

(Side note:  Did you notice how powerful that shift from the use of “he” to the use of “she” was in the first sentence of the paragraph above?  The idea that the manager that we are talking about here is a female feels “off.”  Moreover, the connotation of deceipt and trickery associated with what the active manager is doing in attempting to convince clients that he has special financial talents and that his fund is going to reliably outperform is significantly reduced by imagining the manager as a female.  That’s evidence of ingrained sexual bias, in both directions).

(2) The Framing Power of Fee Extraction:  Fees in the industry get neglected because they are extracted in a psychologically gentle way.  Rather than being charged as a raw monetary amount, they are charged as a percentage of the amount invested.  Additionally, rather than being charged abruptly, in a shocking one-time individual payment, they are taken out gradually, when no one is looking, in teensy-weensy daily increments. As a result, an investor will end up framing the $10,000 fee she might pay on her $1,000,000 investment not as a literal payment of $10,000 that comes directly out of her own pocket, but rather as a negligible skim-off-the-top of a much larger sum of money, taken out when no one is looking, in miniscule incremental shavings that only accumulate to 1% over the course of a full year.

To illustrate the power that this shift in framing has, imagine what would happen if the DOL, in a follow-up to its recent fiduciary interventions, were to require all annual fees to be paid at the end of each year, by a separate check, paid out of a separate account.  Then, instead of having the 1% fee on your $1,000,000 mutual fund investment quietly extracted in imperceptible increments each day, you would have to cut a $10,000 check at the end of each year–go through the process of writing it out, and handing it over to the manager, in exchange for whatever service he provided.  $10,000 is a lot of money to pay to someone that fails to deliver–even for you, a millionaire!

If the way fees are framed were forcibly modified in this way, investors would become extremely averse to paying them.  The ongoing shrinkage of the market’s active segment–in both its size and its fees–would accelerate dramatically.  The effects of the policy might even be so powerful as to push the market into a state in which an acute scarcity of active management ensues–a situation in which everyone attempts to free-ride on the index, and no one steps up to pay the expenses associated with having a well-functioning market.  If that were to happen, active funds would find themselves capable of generating excess returns from the provision of liquidity that substantially exceed the fees they charge. Investors in active funds, who are the only ones actually paying the cost of that service, would begin to receive a benefit for having paid it, a benefit that would be well-deserved.

Posted in Uncategorized | Comments Off on The Paradox of Active Management

有个V字图标免费加速器

The growing popularity of passive investing provokes a series of tough questions:

  • What necessary functions does active management perform in a financial system?
  • What is the optimal amount of active management to have in such a system, to ensure that those functions are carried out?
  • If the size of the market’s active share falls below the optimal level, how will we know?
  • How much can active managers, as a group, reasonably charge for their services, without acting as a net drag on the system?

To answer these questions, I’m going to explore the curious case of Indexville, an economy whose investment sector has been designed to be 100% passive.  As expected, Indexville lacks a number of features that are necessary for the optimal functioning of an economy. I’m going to try to build those features back into it, documenting the cost of doing so each step of the way.  Ultimately, I’m going to run into a problem that ingenuity cannot overcome.  That problem is the exact problem that active management is needed to solve.

A Journey Into Indexville

Indexville is an economy similar in its composition to the United States economy, with one glaring exception: the citizens of Indexville consider active management to be unproductive and immoral, and are therefore invested in Indexville’s corporate sector 100% passively, through a fund called INDX.  The system works as follows:

indexville01

When the citizens of Indexville earn excess cash, they have two options:

(1) Hold it in the bank, where it will earn a small interest rate set by the government–an interest rate of, say, 1% real.

(2) Purchase new shares of the economy’s sole investment vehicle, an index mutual fund called INDX.

When INDX sells new shares to investors, it invests the proceeds in one of four private equity funds–PVT1, PVT2, PVT3, and PVT4.  These private equity funds, which are independently operated, compete with each other to provide equity financing to the corporate sector.   The financing can take the form of either an initial investment, in which a new company is created, or a follow-on investment, in which an existing company is given additional funds for expansion.

教你无痛注册美区 App Store 账号,不需要信用卡和梯子 ...:2021-7-1 · 免信用卡、免梯子,10 分钟即可注册成功。 AppSo(微信号 appsolution)的这篇美国区 Apple ID 的注册教程,是一篇旧文的更新版本,所有的步骤都经过 ...

  • All private sector investments in Indexville are made through the 苹果的梯子 sector, and the financing is always through equity issuance.  There are no homeowners in Indexville, for example–everyone in Indexville rents out homes and apartments from corporations that own them.
  • Direct investment in Indexville’s government sector is not possible.  All federal, state and local Indexville paper is owned by the banking system, which is where the small amount of interest paid to cash depositors ultimately originates.  If investors want a risk-free option, they already have one: hold cash.

For now, we assume that buying INDX shares is a one way transaction.  The shares cannot be redeemed or sold after purchase.  Redeeming them would require de-capitalizing the corporate sector, which is unrealistic.  Trading them with other people is possible, but the option has been made illegal, consistent with Indexville’s moral ethos of total investment passivity: “Thou shalt not trade.”

Now, every existing company in Indexville was created through the above investment process, so INDX owns the ios能用的梯子2022 corporate sector.  That’s what allows us to say that all INDX investors are invested “passively” relative to that sector.  Recall the definition we proposed for a passive allocation:

Passive Allocation: A passive allocation with respect to a given universe of assets is an allocation that holds every asset in that universe in relative proportion to the the total quantity of the asset in existence.

The total quantity of corporate assets in Indexville literally is INDX.  Whatever the relative proportion between the quantities of the different assets inside INDX happens to be, every investor will own them in that relative proportion, ios可众用的梯子 by owning INDX shares.

Now, to be fair, the investors in INDX are not passively allocated relative to the entire universe of Indexville’s financial assets, which includes both equity and cash.  Though such an allocation might be possible to achieve, it would clearly be impossible to maintain in practice.  Anytime anyone spent any money, the spender would decrease his cash, and the recipient would increase it, throwing off any previously passive allocation that might have existed.

The word “passive” can take on another important sense in these discussions, which is the sense associated with a “passive ethos”, where investors refrain from placing trades for speculative reasons, and instead only trade as necessary to carry out their saving and consumption plans, or to transition their portfolios to a state that matches their risk tolerances as they age.  This is the sense of the term found in the advice of the gurus of “passive” investing–Jack Bogle, Burton Malkiel, Eugene Fama, and so on.  Indexville investors follow that advice, and fully embrace a “passive ethos.”

ios能用的梯子2021 - 苹果软件--免费绿色软件下载,共享软件 ...:2021-5-1 · ios能用的梯子2021一款100%免费,无限制,安全保证,超级好用。您可众连接到众下任何服务器(瑞典,英国,丹麦,法国,美国,荷兰和加拿大)的尽情享受无限制的在线隐私和自由。使用VPN

Instead of relying on equity issuance, corporations in Indexville have the option of funding new investment out of their own profits.  When they choose to do that, they reduce the dividends that they are able to pay to the private equity funds, which in turn reduces the dividends that the private equity funds are able to pay to INDX investors.  But the reduction is compensated for in the long-term, because the new investment produces real growth in future profits, which leads to real growth in future dividends paid.

Cost #1: Conducting Due-Diligence on New Investment Opportunities

To make sound investments–whether in new companies seeking initial capital, or in existing companies seeking follow-on capital–the private equity funds have to conduct appropriate due-diligence on candidate investment opportunities.  That due diligence requires research, which costs money–the funds have to hire smart people to go and do it.

Where will the money to pay these people come from?  Unfortunately, Indexville’s passive structure has no magic bullet to offer here–the money will have to come from the only place that it can come from: out of investor returns, as fees.  It will get subtracted from the dividends paid to the private equity funds, and therefore from the dividends paid to INDX, and therefore from the dividends paid to investors.

What we’ve identified, then, is the first unavoidable cost of a 100% passive system:

Cost #1: The need to pay people to conduct appropriate due-diligence on new investment opportunities, so as to ensure that INDX investor capital is allocated productively and profitably, at the best possible price.

Note that Cost #1 is not driven by a need to put a “trading” price on already-existing companies.  The trading prices of such companies do not matter to INDX investors, since INDX already fully owns them, and has no one to sell them to but itself.  Nor do the prices matter to the economy, because the physical capital that underlies them has already been formed.  The price that people decide to trade that capital at does not affect its underlying productivity.

The need that gives rise to Cost #1 is the need to determine whether a company is an appropriate target for new investment–taking new investor funds, new economic resources, and putting them into a startup, or a struggling company–and whether the investment will produce a better return than other available opportunities, given the proposed price.  Mistakes made in that determination have a direct negative impact on investor performance, and lead to suboptimal allocation of the economy’s labor and capital resources.

Let’s ask: what is a reasonable estimate of the total expense associated with Cost #1?  How much should we expect it to detract from INDX’s returns? The answer will depend on how much new investment the private equity funds engage in. Recall that most of the investment in Indexville will be carried out by already-existing companies, using retained profits as the funding source. The cost of the research done in association with that investment is already reflected in the net profits of the companies.

The U.S. has roughly 5,000 publicly-traded companies.  To be conservative, let’s assume that Indexville’s corporate sector is similarly sized, and that 1,000 companies–20% of the total–seek new funding each year, either in initial public offerings or, more commonly, in follow-on offerings.  We want Indexville’s capital to be allocated as productively as possible, so we assign two extremely talented analysts to each company, at an annual cost of $300,000–$200,000 in salary, and $100,000 in capital investment to support the research process.  For a full year, the analysts spend the entirety of every workday researching their assigned individual company, rigorously weighing the investment opportunity. The resulting cost:

1000 * 2* $300,000 = $600,000,000.

The U.S. equity market is valued at roughly $30T.  Expressed as a percentage of that overall total, the annual cost of investment due diligence in Indexville amounts to ios可众用的梯子 of total assets.

Of course, we want to have the benefits of aggressive competition in Indexville.  So we multiply that cost by 4, to reflect the fact that each of the four funds will carry out the research program independently, in competition with each other.  To be clear, then, the four funds will each have 2,000 analysts–8,000 in total–who each spend an entire year effectively researching one-half of a single investment opportunity, at a cost of $300,000 per analyst per year.  The total annual expense: 0.008% of total marketable assets.

Consistent with Indexville’s emphasis on engineered competition, an advisory board for INDX has been created.  Its responsibility is to evaluate the long-term investment performances of the four private equity funds, and adjust the amount of future funding provided to them accordingly.  Funds that have made good investments get a larger share of the future investment pie, funds that have made bad investments get a smaller share. Similar adjustments are made to manager pay.  Managers of strongly performing funds see their pay increased, managers of poorly performing funds see their pay decreased.

What will the advisory board cost?  Assuming 50 people on it, at an annual cost of $500,000 per person, we get $25MM, which is 0.00008% of assets–in other words, nothing.

Cost #2: Determining a Correct Price for INDX Shares

When investors buy new shares in INDX, they have to buy at a price.  How is that price determined?  Recall that Indexville’s corporate sector is entirely private. There is no market for the individual companies.  Nor is there a market for INDX shares. It follows that the only way to value INDX shares is to calculate the value of each underlying company, one by one, summing the results together to get the total.  That’s going to cost money.

So we arrive at the 苹果翻墙梯子 unavoidable cost of a 100% passive system:

Cost #2: The need to pay people to determine the values of the individual companies in the index, so that new shares of the index can be sold to investors at fair prices.

Cost #1 was a worthwhile cost.  The underlying work it entailed was worth doing in order to maximize INDX shareholder returns and ensure efficient capital allocation in Indexville’s economy.  Cost #2, in contrast, is a net drag on the system.  It has no offsetting benefit, and can be avoided if the participants embrace a cooperative mentality.

Suppose that a mistake is made in the calculation of INDX’s price, and an investor ends up paying slightly more for INDX shares than he should have paid.  The investor will see a slight reduction in his returns.  That reduction, of course, will occur alongside a slight increase in the returns of existing investors, who will have taken in funds at a premium.  In the end, the aggregate impact on the returns of the system will be zero, because price-setting is a zero-sum game.

Now, the direct, short-term impact of pricing mistakes may be zero-sum, but the long-term effect can be negative, particularly if the mistakes cause people to alter their future behaviors in undesirable ways.  If consistent inaccuracies are tolerated, people might try to find ways to “game” them.  They might also become disgruntled, and cease to participate in the investment process.  If that’s what’s going to happen, then we’re not going to have much of a choice: we’re going to have to spend the money needed to make sure the price is as right as it can be, for every new share sale, every day.  The cost will come out of everyone’s return, reflecting the drag on the system brought about by the non-cooperative mentality.

Given that Indexville’s corporate sector is roughly the same size as the public market of the United States, the task of accurately calculating the fund’s price will entail valuing roughly 5,000 individual companies.  The proposed plan is as follows.  As before, we hire two highly talented analysts for each company.  We give each analyst the singular responsibility of building a valuation estimate for the company, and adjusting the estimate on a daily basis to reflect any new information that becomes available.  The basic instruction to each analyst is:

  • Develop an estimate of the company’s future cash flows, and discount those cash flows at a required real rate of 6%, which is what Indexville investors consider to be a fair return.  Focus on getting the cash flows right.  Your pay will be tied to how well you do that.
  • Where there is uncertainty, identify the different possibilities, and weigh them by their probabilities.  Do not let the desire to be right in your past analysis influence your future analysis–instead, respond to the facts as they present themselves, with a singular focus on truth, i.e., “what is actually going to happen?”, rather than “what do I personally want to happen?”  If necessary, examine past valuation work done on similar companies, especially work done by top-performing analysts, and use their insights to help you triangulate towards a reasonable number.
  • iphone苹果如何打开Youtube可众用的苹果翻墙油管知乎免费 ...:解决苹果手机如何上Youtube,ipad如何打开Youtube,ios怎么注册Youtube油管,2021电脑PC端可众用的稳定vpn账号密码翻墙软件美国香港ios苹果iphone手机梯子安卓Android节点知乎免费推荐国外付费ssr科学上网游戏视频vpn路由器账号密码

【IOS】手把手教你如何登陆switch online【无需梯...:2021-4-22 · 应该是就两种办法吧:1.搭梯子 把图从switch直接上传到twitter或fb后用手机下载看;2.用读卡器把 应该是就两种办法吧:1.搭梯子 把图从switch直接上传到twitter或fb后用手机下载看;2.用读卡器把相册的图导出来... 元気少女俊一基

How much will this project cost annually?

5,000 * 2 * $300,000 = $3,000,000,000

But let’s assume that we really want to get the final numbers right, to ensure fairness for all Indexville investors.  So we ios能用的梯子2022 the effort.  We put four analysts on every company, instead of two.  The result:

5,000 * 4 * $300,000 = $6,000,000,000

So, $6,000,000,000.  Relative to the (assumed) total market capitalization of Indexville’s universe of companies, $30T, the cost represents 0.02% of assets.

Now, you might think that an actual market’s estimate of corporate value will be more accurate than the estimates of these 20,000 analysts.  But you have no evidence of that. What would evidence even look like?  Markets don’t publish their “future cash flow estimates”, nor do they reveal their “discount rates.”  These artifacts can only be arrived at tautologically, by extracting them together from the price.  And either way, it doesn’t matter.  As long as the citizen’s of Indexville believe that the estimates of the 20,000 analysts are accurate, and maintain their trust in the system, actual inaccuracies will not affect anything, because price-setting, again, is a zero-sum game.

Cost #3: The Provision of Liquidity

[IOS]:免费梯子应用,纯美国低延迟推荐。 - 优创博客:2021-6-11 · 前言因为之前某些原因,所众启明星辰没有再开放。梯子目前需要用到的地方还是很多,不仅仅是可众去看墙外的世界。今天优哥给小伙伴伔分享一个免费的美区V-P-N。【来自优创小伙伴推荐】应用介绍来自美区的...

  • The first was the cost of conducting due-diligence on new investment opportunties. Actual cost: 0.008% of assets.
  • The second was the cost of valuing existing companies in the fund so as to determine a fair sale price for new shares.  Actual cost: 0.02% of assets.

Both costs proved to be extremely small.  Clearly, then, a large active segment is not needed to solve them, especially not at typical active fee levels, which can be anywhere from 25 to 100 times higher.

Unfortunately, there’s a huge problem with Indexville’s system that we haven’t addressed: the problem of liquidity.  An investor can convert cash into INDX by purchasing shares, but what if an investor wants to go the other way, and convert INDX shares back into cash?  In its current configuration, Indexville doesn’t offer the option to do that.

Unlike money, or even a debt security, an equity security is intrinsically illiquid.  It has no maturity date, and offers no direct method of redemption.  The cash that went into purchasing it is effectively gone.  The only way to directly get that cash back is to have the corporate sector liquidate–a solution that is not realistically possible, and that would require investors to take losses if it were.

What is the real cost of the illiquidity of an equity security?  Answer: the inconvenience imposed on the owner.  The owner has to factor the cost of the illiquidity into his pricing of the security.  If he is making an investment in a new company, and is taking a full equity stake in it, he will have to require a higher future return–higher not to make the overall deal any better for him, but simply to compensate him for the significant drawback associated with losing his ability to access his money.  The higher return hurdle that he will be forced to place on the process will disqualify investment prospects that would otherwise be beneficial to everyone, if they were liquid.  Similarly, if he is making an investment in an existing company owned by someone else, he is going to have to demand a lower price for his stake.  That lower price will come at the existing owner’s expense, rendering the issuance less attractive to the existing owner, and causing him to not want to take in funds and make investments that would otherwise be beneficial to everyone, if liquidity existed.

The cost of illiquidity is real, and therefore it’s important that we find a way to make INDX liquid.  So here’s a simple proposal: we give investors an option to sell–not to other people, but to INDX directly, in a mutual fund redemption process.  Every day, at the end of the day, we pair buyers and sellers of the fund, exchanging the incoming cash and the existing shares between them.  If you are seeking to buy, I pair you with a seller.  You take his shares, he takes your cash.  And vice-versa.  This won’t cost us anything extra, because we already know the fair value of the fund from the prior calculations that we paid for. Investors will then have liquidity.

Indexville’s citizens are likely to be averse to this suggestion, because it enables the toxic practice of market timing.  But there are legitimate, non-speculative reasons why an investor may want to sell shares.  For example, the investor may be entering a later of phase of her life, and may want to withdraw the funds to spend them down.  Either that, or she may simply prefer a more liquid allocation, and be willing to give up some return in exchange for it.  Some other investor may have similarly legitimate reasons for wanting to buy new shares–the investor might be in a younger phase of life, and have a greater need to save, or want more growth.  What is the harm in pairing the two together, exchanging the shares and cash between them?  The exchange may be zero-sum in terms of how the future returns get divided, but it will be positive sum in terms of its overall impact–both investors will end up winners.  This contrasts with a scenario where the two investors trade for speculative reasons, because one thinks the price is going to rise, and the other thinks the price is going to fall.  That trade will be zero-sum.  One trader is going to be right, and the other trader is going to be equally wrong.

Let’s assume that we’re able to convince the citizens of Indexville that there are legitimate uses for liquidity, and that everyone will ultimately benefit from the introduction of a sale option in INDX shares.  We’re still going to run into a problem.  How will the fund deal with periods in which there is more buying than selling, or more selling than buying?  In those periods, excess buyers and sellers will end up leftover, with orders that cannot be met. What will the fund do with them?

If there is more buying than selling, the fund can always issue new shares.  But the private equity firms may not need new funds.  There may not be any attractive investment opportunities–with returns of 6% or better–for them to deploy the funds into.  If we allow new shares to be created at 6%, when there are no 6%-or-better investments for the funds to invest in, we will be harming existing shareholders, diluting their stakes in exchange for nothing.

If there is more selling than buying, the situation becomes more complicated.  One option is to take the cash dividends of other investors, and give those dividends to the sellers, in exchange for their stake.  On this option, the existing investors will effectively be “reinvesting” their dividends.  But they may not want to do that.  And even if they do want to do it, the dividend payments in a given quarter may not be enough to fully meet the selling demand.  Another option would be for INDX to borrow cash to pay exiting shareholders.  On this option, the remaining investors will essentially be levering up their stakes.  Again, they may not want to do that.   And even if they do want to do it, the option of borrowing for that purpose may not be something that the banking system in Indexville is willing to make available.

Apart from forced dividend reinvestment and forced leveraging, the only other way for INDX to get the cash needed to pay the exiting investors would be to have the corporate sector liquidate, i.e., sell itself.  But, again, assuming that all of the capital that went into the funds and companies has been deployed, who exactly are the companies going to sell themselves to?  INDX is the only possible buyer, and it has no cash.  It’s trying to get cash, to redeem the investors that want to sell it.

A final option would be for INDX to change its price.  Instead of having investors exchange shares at a price associated with an implied rate of return of 6%, it could raise or lower the price–i.e., decrease or increase the implied rate of return–in order to discourage buying or selling and balance the demand.  Unfortunately, that won’t work.  Indexville’s investors are entirely passive.  They make investment decisions based on their personal savings and consumption needs, not based on valuation arbitrage, which they do not understand. INDX can raise its price to infinity, or drop its prize to zero–either way, the buying and selling demand of the system will not change.  The only thing that will change is that certain unlucky people will end up getting screwed–denied the “fair value” return that they deserve, 6%.

With the above options ruled out, INDX’s only remaining option will be to simply say no:

“We’ve received your sale order.  Due to market conditions, we are not currently able to execute it.  However, we’ve placed your name in a queue.  Currently, you are number 47 in the queue, with $400MM worth of selling demand in front of you.  Once we’ve found buyers to take on that selling demand, any subsequent buy orders will be routed through you.”

The problem with this option, of course, is that it represents a loss of investor liquidity. Investors will only have guaranteed immediate liquidity if they are lucky enough to be going against the prevailing investment flows.  Otherwise, they will have to wait.

But would that really create a problem?  It would certainly create a problem if Indexville’s investors were inclined to trade for speculative reasons.  The mere perception of impending excess buying or selling demand would incent them to buy or sell, reflexively exacerbating the ensuing flow imbalance.  But Indexville’s investors are not like that. Consistent with Indexville’s passive ethos, they only make trades for legitimate personal reasons–because they have savings to invest, or because they need to draw down on their savings in order to fund their lifestyles.

In certain situations where a large imbalance naturally develops in the economy’s saving preferences, the answer is, yes, it would create a problem.  One can imagine, for example, a scenario in which the average age of Indexville’s citizenry increases dramatically, resulting in a large population of older people with a preference for redeeming shares, and only a small population of younger people with a preference for purchasing them.  In such a scenario, the older generation will lose its liquidity.  But as long as Indexville’s economy remains capable of producing what its citizens want and need, any ensuing problem will be illusory–a problem that results entirely from the accounting artifacts–“shares”, “cash”, etc.–that are being used to divide up the economy’s purchasing power.  Policy intervention could easily solve it–for example, by having the government print cash and purchase the shares from the older generation at fair value.

Now, everything I’ve just said is based on the assumption that Indexville’s investors are fully passive, that they do not respond to valuation arbitrage.  If that’s not true, i.e., if they have even the 苹果手机用的梯子 of speculative instincts, then the problems with the above proposal will compound.  Assuming that Indexville’s economic condition is similar to the current economic condition of the United States, the discount rate at which prices for the fund have been set, 6%, will be too high relative to the small interest rate, 1%, that can be earned on the alternative, cash.  The economy will not have a sufficient quantity of investment opportunities, with returns of 6% or better, in order to meet that saving demand.  INDX will therefore see a persistent excess of buying–especially if the buyers are reflexively aware that the economy’s strong saving demand will guarantee them future liquidity, should they ever want to sell.

But if Indexville’s investors are active, and respond to valuation arbitrage, then a previously discarded solution will work just fine.  All that INDX will have to do to balance the flows is change the price at which purchase and sale orders are executed.  If there is too much buying demand, raise the price–the lower implied return will lead to a reduction in buying demand.  If there is too little buying demand, lower the price–the higher implied return will increase the buying demand.  Of course, to embrace this solution, Indexville’s investors are going to have to abandon the notion that anything other than a 6% return is “unfair.”  If there is strong demand for saving in the economy, and if the private equity funds cannot find sufficient investment opportunities with a return above 6% to deploy that saving into, then lower returns will simply have to be accepted.

In the above case, there are tools that the government can use to create higher returns for investors.  But those tools come with separate costs.  It doesn’t make sense for the society to offer to bear those costs simply to improve the average investor’s lot.  The right answer is for investors to 苹果翻墙梯子 lower rates of return, which is fair compensation for their investment contributions, given the economy’s ios可众用的梯子 need for them.

Returning to the assumption that Indexville’s investors are completely passive and insensitive to arbitrage, there will be no way to address flow imbalances other than by make people wait their turn.  The cost of that approach is lost liquidity.

Cost #3: the cost of providing liquidity in situations where the legitimately passive buying and selling flows going into and out of the index fail to balance out.

Unfortunately, there is no amount of money that Indexville can spend to cover that cost, i.e., to provide the desired liquidity.  For Indexville to have it, some investor somewhere will have to agree to go active.

Market-Making and Active Management

When you place an order in the market to buy a share of stock, how do you place it?  If you’re like most people, you place it either as a market order, or as a limit order above the lowest ask price.  You do that because you want the order to execute.  You want to buy now.  If you thought that a better time to buy would come later, you would just wait.

Instead of insisting on buying now, why don’t you just put a limit order in to buy below the prevailing price, and go on about your business?  Because you’re not stupid.  To put in a limit order below the market price, and then walk away, would be to give the rest of the market a 100% free put option on the stock, at your expense.  If the stock goes higher, the gains will end up going to someone else.  If the stock goes lower, you will end up buying it, and will get stuck with the losses.  Why would you agree to a let someone else have the gains on an investment, while you take the losses?

But wait.  There was a limit order to sell that was just sitting there–specifically, the order that you intentionally placed your buy price above, so as to guarantee an execution.  Where did that order come from?  Who was the person that just stuck it in there, and walked away?  What was his thinking?

The person who put that order in, of course, was the market-maker–the person who does the work necessary to create a liquid market.  Market orders do not come into the system at the same time.  Someone therefore has to bridge them together.  That is what a market-maker does.  When no one else is around, he puts a bid order in to buy at some price, and an ask order in to sell at some price, slightly higher.  He then waits for those that want to trade now to come in and take his orders.  In each round-trip transaction, each buy followed by a sell, he earns a spread, the spread between his bid and ask.

The following equation quantifies his revenue:

Revenue = 1/2 * Volume * Spread

So that is his revenue.  What is his cost?

His first cost is the cost of doing the work necessary to find out where the right price for the market is.  To ensure that he earns the spread, he has to identify the balancing point for the market, the general level at which the buying flow and the selling flow will roughly match.  That is the level around which he has to place his orders, so that roughly the same number of people buy from him as sell to him.  If he fails to target that level correctly–i.e., if he places his bid and ask orders at levels where the flows will become imbalanced–he will end up accumulating unwanted inventory.

mktflow

His second cost is the cost of being wrong on the correct market price.  If he is wrong, and ends up accumulating unwanted inventory, he will have to either hold that inventory indefinitely, or liquidate it, both of which will occur at a cost.  To mitigate the impact of that cost, the market-maker will have to do at least a minimal amount of work to assess the value of what he is offering to hold.  He has to know what it’s actually worth, in some fundamental sense, in case he gets stuck holding it.

p站(Pixiv)无需科学上网(不用VPN翻墙梯子)也能正常在线 ...:2021-6-13 · 2 最新版Mac OS 10.15.5 黑苹果系统分享,直链下载,无需任何密码 3 Mac OS Catalina 10.15.4 黑苹果系统分享,直链下载,无需任何密码 4 p站(Pixiv)无需科学上网(不用VPN翻墙梯子)也能正常在线打开的方法分享 5 百度SEO算法大盘点(2021-5-28日更新)

What Indexville needs is for an active investor to step up and become a market-maker for INDX, so that temporary imbalances in the quantities of buyers and sellers can be smoothed out.  The market-maker needs to figure out the patterns that define INDX transactions: When does there tend to be too much buying?  When does there tend to be too much selling?  If the market-maker can correctly answer those questions, he can ios翻外墙用什么 the excesses together, eliminating them through his trades.  That is what it means to “provide liquidity.”

Given that Indexville’s investors are passive and unresponsive to arbitrage, a potential market-maker won’t even have to worry about what the right price point for INDX shares is.  All that will matter is the future trajectory of the flow imbalances, which is entirely set by non-speculative preferences.  If the market-maker can accurately anticipate that trajectory, he will be able to set the price wherever he wants, earning as much profit as he wants, 苹果翻墙梯子 having to unbalance his own holdings.

Will Indexville’s investors get bilked in this arrangement?  No.  If the market-maker imposes an unreasonably high spread–only offering to buy shares, for example, at an 8% implied return, and only offering to sell them, for example, at a 4% implied return–then other potential active investors will take note of his outsized profits, and enter the fray to compete with him, becoming market-makers themselves.  They will jump in front of his bids and asks, forcing him to either compress his spread, or let them get the executions. They will also force him to do more research, because they will now be there to arbitrage his mistakes.  Ultimately, the revenue that he is able to earn, and that the Indexville investment community will have to pay him, will converge on his cost of doing business, which is the cost of studying and understanding the market, figuring out what the underlying securities are actually worth, and risking the possibility of getting stuck with someone else’s illiquidity.

Notice that these are the same costs that, up to now, Indexville has had to pay separately, given that it has no active investors. When active investors enter to make a market, the costs no longer need to be paid separately–the active investors can provide the associated services, with the rest of the market compensating them in the form of market-making profits.

Enter Warren Buffett

In February of this year, Druce Vertes of StreetEye wrote an exceptionally lucid and insightful piece on the topic of Active Management.  In it, he asked the following question: what would happen if everyone in the market except Warren Buffett were to go passive? He showed, correctly, that Buffett could still beat the market.

In the scenario, when the passive segment of the market wants to sell, Buffett is the only potential buyer.  Buffett is therefore able to demand a low price, a discount to fair value.  When the passive segment wants to buy, Buffett is again the only potential seller.  He is therefore able to demand a high price, a premium to fair value.  On each go-round, each shift from passive net selling to passive net buying, Buffett buys significantly below fair value, and sells significantly above it, generating the superior returns that he is famous for.

What is Buffet doing in this example? He is earning the outsized revenues that inevitably come when you provide liquidity to a market that needs it. Those revenues easily cover the cost of providing that liquidity, which is the cost of understanding the psychology of the passive investors, so as to anticipate their net flows, and also the cost of determining the fair value of the underlying securities, to know what prices he can prudently pay for them, in case he gets stuck holding them.

p站(Pixiv)无需科学上网(不用VPN翻墙梯子)也能正常在线 ...:2021-6-13 · 2 最新版Mac OS 10.15.5 黑苹果系统分享,直链下载,无需任何密码 3 Mac OS Catalina 10.15.4 黑苹果系统分享,直链下载,无需任何密码 4 p站(Pixiv)无需科学上网(不用VPN翻墙梯子)也能正常在线打开的方法分享 5 百度SEO算法大盘点(2021-5-28日更新)

The Value of Active Management

In the previous two pieces, we expressed the Law of Conservation of Alpha, attributable to William Sharpe:

The Law of Conservation of Alpha: Before fees, the average performance of the investors that make up the active segment of a market will always equal the average performance of the investors that make up the passive segment.

西语助手|西汉-汉西词典 梯子是什么意思_梯子的西语解释和 ...:他伔登上 梯子 去摘高枝上的苹果 。Aquí hay una escalera. 这里有一架 梯子。声明:众上例句、词性 类均由互联网资源自动生成,部 未经过人工审核,其表达内容亦不伕表本软件的 ...

The Law of Conservation of Alpha, *With Liquidity: Before fees, the average performance of the investors that make up the active segment of a market will exceed the average performance of the investors that make up the passive segment, by an amount equal to the market-making profits that the active segment earns in providing liquidity to the passive segment.

With this law in hand, we are now in a position to answer the four questions posed at the outset.

First, what necessary functions does active management perform in a financial system?

ios能用的梯子2022: The function of providing liquidity to the market, specifically to the passive segment, and to companies seeking funding.  In seeking to fulfill that function profitably, the active segment ends up providing the other functions of ensuring that new investment capital is correctly allocated and that existing assets get correctly priced, functions that Indexville had to pay for separately, because it lacked an active segment.

蛇和梯子世界版app下载_蛇和梯子世界版ios版v1.0-游迅网 ...:2021-12-3 · 蛇和梯子世界版下载,蛇和梯子世界版是一款卡通益智游戏,准备玩最流行的经典棋盘游戏--蛇和梯子!这种独特的游戏激发了许多改编,出现了几个角色,包括滑道和梯子。但没有什么是接近原来的经典。我伔为苹果提供的蛇和梯子都是在两个单人和双人格式。

Second, what is the optimal amount of active management to have in a financial system, to ensure that those functions are carried out?

Answer: The amount needed to ensure that adequate liquidity is provided to the market, specifically to the passive segment of the market and to companies seeking funding, assuming that the passive segment is not structured to provide that funding (as it was in Indexville).  If there is adequate liquidity, prices will tend to be correct; if they are incorrect, those participants that are causing them to be incorrect will be exposed to arbitrage by other participants, which will render their liquidity provision unprofitable.

At this point it’s important to note that self-described “passive” investors are themselves the ones that determine how much active management will be needed.  If the segment of the market that is proudly calling itself “passive” right now is only going to embrace “passivity” while things are good, morphing itself into an active, speculative, market-timing operation as soon as things turn sour, then a large number of active investors will be needed to come bail it out.  As a group, those active investors will get the opportunity to earn their fees and outperform.  But if investors come to their senses, and take a long view similar to the one embraced in Indexville, then the market’s liquidity needs will be minimal, and a market with a small active segment will be able to function just fine.

Third, if the size of the market’s active share falls below the optimal level, how will we know?

Answer: The market will show signs of not having enough liquidity.

If there is an insufficient amount of active management in the system, then whenever the passive segment introduces a net flow, prices will take on wild swings, and will become substantially disconnected from fair value.  The problem, however, will be self-correcting, because there will then be a greater financial incentive for investors to go active and take advantage of the lucractive reward being offered for providing liquidity.  The active segment as a whole will see stronger performance.

Fourth, how much can active managers, as a group, reasonably charge for their services, without acting as a net drag on the system?

Answer: An amount equal to the excess profit that they are able to earn in providing liquidity to the market, specifically to passive investors and companies seeking funding.

The active segment needs to earn its fees.  If it can’t earn its fees, then there will always be an arbitrage opportunity putting pressure on its size.  Investors will be able to get higher returns by going passive, and that’s what they’ll do.

The only way the active segment, as a group, can earn its fees, is by providing liquidity to the market, specifically to the passive segment, and to corporations seeking new funding. Of course, the active segment can trade with itself, attempting to arbitrage its own mistakes in that effort, but for every winner there will be a loser, and the net profit for the group will be nothing.  Any fees charged in the ensuing cannibalization will represent a loss to investors relative to the alternative–which is to simply go passive.

In terms of the larger benefit to society, the cannibalization may cause prices to become more “correct”, but how “correct” do they need to be?  And why does their “correctness” require such an enormous and expensive struggle?  Recall that in Indexville we were able to buy a decent substitute for the struggle–a 20,000-person army of highly talented analysts valuing the market–for a tiny fraction of the cost.

If we shrink down the size of the active segment of the market, it becomes easier for that segment to earn its fees through the liquidity that it provides–which it has to do in order to collapse the arbitrage, particularly if its fees are going to remain high as a percentage of its assets.  That is the path to an equilibrium in which active and passive generate the same return, net of fees, and in which there is no longer a reason to prefer one over the other.

Summary: Putting Everything Together

The points that I’ve tried to express in this piece are complex and difficult to clearly convey.  So I’m going to summarize them in bullet points below:

  • The right size of the active segment of the market is the size that allows it to earn whatever fees it charges.  If it cannot earn those fees, then there will always be an arbitrage opportunity putting pressure on its size.  Investors will be able to get higher returns by going passive, and so that’s what they’ll do.
  • The only way the active segment, as a group, can earn its fees, is by providing liquidity to the market, specifically to the passive segment, and to corporations seeking new funding.  All other profits for the segment will be zero-sum.
  • The question that determines the necessary amount of active management is this: how much natural passive flow is there in the system, i.e., non-speculative flow associated with people wanting to save excess income, or wanting to consume out of savings, or wanting to alter their risk allocations, given changes in their ages?  Similarly, what is the natural corporate demand for funding?  That flow, and that demand for funding, represents active management’s potential market for the provision of liquidity.  Relative to the actual volume that takes place in the current market, it is minimal.
  • If the investing ethos evolves such that market participants become decreasingly inclined towards active behaviors–i.e., if they learn their lessons, and stop making trades for speculative reasons, and instead take the sage advice of a Bogle, or a Malkiel, or a Fama to limit their interventions to cases where they have legitimate non-speculative reasons for modifying their portfolios–then the active segment will have to shrink ios可众用的梯子 from its current size.  Either that, or it will have to shrink its fees.
  • At some point in the above scenario–which, to be clear, is the Indexville scenario–the system will get to down to some bare-bones minimum level of active management, a level at which active managers, as a group, will be small enough to earn excess profits that are sufficient to cover the percentage-based fees they charge.  Where is that minimum level?  In my view, far away from the current level, at least at current fee rates.  If I had to randomly guess, I would say somewhere in the range of 5% active, 95% passive.  If we include private equity in the active universe, then maybe the number is higher–say, 10% active, 90% passive.
  • On the other hand, if we assume that the trend towards “passive investing” is simply about investors in the current bull market falling in love with $SPY or $VFIAX given the recent performance of U.S. equities, rather than about investors actually committing to the advice of a Bogle, or a Malkiel, or a Fama–then the future liquidity that those investors will consume when they change their minds will provide opportunities for what we’re calling the “active segment” to step in and earn its fees.  But this point will be purely definitional, because the investors we are calling “passive”, though technically passive relative to the S&P 500, will not have been 苹果手机用的梯子passive at all, in terms of the spirit of what that term means.  They will have been active investors operating in guise, who just-so-happened to have been using index-based instruments in their efforts.
Posted in Uncategorized | Comments Off on The Value of Active Management: A Journey Into Indexville